Эпоха просвещения как пишется

Навигация

§ 17. Названия исторических эпох, событий, съездов, геологических периодов

1. В названиях исторических эпох и событий первое слово (и все имена собственные) пишется с прописной буквы; родовые наименования (эпоха, век и т. п.) пишутся со строчной буквы: Древний Китай, Древняя Греция, Древний Рим (‘государство’; но: древний Рим — ‘город’), Римская империя, Киевская Русь; Крестовые походы, эпоха Возрождения, Высокое Возрождение, Ренессанс, Реформация, эпоха Просвещения, Смутное время, Петровская эпоха (но: допетровская эпоха, послепетровская эпоха); Куликовская битва, Бородинский бой; Семилетняя война, Великая Отечественная война (традиционное написание), Война за независимость (в Северной Америке); Июльская монархия, Вторая империя, Пятая республика; Парижская коммуна, Версальский мир, Декабрьское вооружённое восстание 1905 года (но: декабрьское восстание 1825 года).

2. В официальных названиях конгрессов, съездов, конференций первое слово (обычно это слова Первый, Второй и т. д.; Всероссийский, Всесоюзный, Всемирный, Международный и т. п.) и все имена собственные пишутся с прописной буквы: Всероссийский съезд учителей, Первый всесоюзный съезд писателей, Всемирный конгресс сторонников мира, Международный астрономический съезд, Женевская конференция, Базельский конгресс I Интернационала.

После порядкового числительного, обозначенного цифрой, сохраняется написание первого слова с прописной буквы: 5-й Международный конгресс преподавателей, XX Международный Каннский кинофестиваль.

3. Названия исторических эпох, периодов и событий, не являющиеся именами собственными, а также названия геологических периодов пишутся со строчной буквы: античный мир, средневековье, феодализм, русско-турецкие войны, наполеоновские войны; гражданская война (но: Гражданская война в России и США); мезозойская эра, меловой период, эпоха палеолита, каменный век, ледниковый период.

Как правильно пишется словосочетание «эпоха просвещения»

  • Как правильно пишется слово «эпоха»
  • Как правильно пишется слово «просвещение»

Делаем Карту слов лучше вместе

Привет! Меня зовут Лампобот, я компьютерная программа, которая помогает делать
Карту слов. Я отлично
умею считать, но пока плохо понимаю, как устроен ваш мир. Помоги мне разобраться!

Спасибо! Я стал чуточку лучше понимать мир эмоций.

Вопрос: растровый — это что-то нейтральное, положительное или отрицательное?

Ассоциации к слову «эпоха»

Ассоциации к слову «просвещение»

Синонимы к словосочетанию «эпоха просвещения»

Предложения со словосочетанием «эпоха просвещения»

  • А потом где-то в середине тысячелетия началась эпоха просвещения – проявленного света.
  • Что касается физики, то мы нападём и на новую физику 21века, и на физику элементарных частиц 20 века, а самое удивительное, даже на классическую физику эпохи просвещения.
  • Но с возникновением науки, изучением истории после эпохи просвещения судьба человечества стала рассматриваться как единая история развития и прогресса вместе с препятствиями, периодами застоя и регресса, которые, разумеется, вполне возможны.
  • (все предложения)

Цитаты из русской классики со словосочетанием «эпоха просвещения»

  • — Нет-с, дала ответ, дала в том, как думали лучшие умы, как думали Вольтер [Вольтер (Франсуа Мари Аруэ) (1694—1778) — выдающийся французский писатель, один из крупнейших деятелей эпохи Просвещения.], Конт.
  • Позади его не было Средневековья, позади была пережитая интеллигенцией эпоха просвещения.
  • Русский ренессанс вернее сравнить с германским романтизмом начала XIX в., которому тоже предшествовала эпоха просвещения.
  • (все
    цитаты из русской классики)

Сочетаемость слова «эпоха»

  • новая эпоха
    советская эпоха
    целая эпоха
  • эпоха возрождения
    эпоха просвещения
    эпоха ренессанса
  • люди разных эпох
    начало новой эпохи
    конец эпохи
  • эпоха закончилась
    эпоха кончилась
    эпоха сменилась
  • жить в эпоху
    относиться к эпохе
    начиная с эпохи
  • (полная таблица сочетаемости)

Сочетаемость слова «просвещение»

  • народное просвещение
    европейское просвещение
    французское просвещение
  • просвещение народа
    просвещение масс
    просвещение ума
  • эпоха просвещения
    министерство народного просвещения
    министр народного просвещения
  • заняться чьим-либо просвещением
    начиная с эпохи просвещения
    нести просвещение
  • (полная таблица сочетаемости)

Значение словосочетания «эпоха просвещения»

  • Эпо́ха Просвеще́ния — одна из ключевых эпох в истории европейской культуры, связанная с развитием научной, философской и общественной мысли. В основе этого интеллектуального движения лежали рационализм и свободомыслие. (Википедия)

    Все значения словосочетания ЭПОХА ПРОСВЕЩЕНИЯ

Афоризмы русских писателей со словом «эпоха»

  • А там, меж строк,
    Минуя и ахи и охи,
    Тебе улыбнется презрительно Блок —
    Трагический тенор эпохи.
  • Никакой язык ни в какую эпоху не может быть до того удовлетворительным, чтобы от него нечего было больше желать и ожидать.
  • Литературы великих мировых эпох таят в себе присутствие чего-то страшного, то приближающегося, то опять, отходящего, наконец разражающегося смерчем где-то совсем близко, так близко, что, кажется, почва уходит из-под ног: столб крутящейся пыли вырывает воронки в земле и уносит вверх окружающие цветы и травы. Тогда кажется, что близок конец и не может более существовать литература. Она сметена смерчем, разразившемся в душе писателя.
  • (все афоризмы русских писателей)

Отправить комментарий

Дополнительно

Смотрите также

Эпо́ха Просвеще́ния — одна из ключевых эпох в истории европейской культуры, связанная с развитием научной, философской и общественной мысли. В основе этого интеллектуального движения лежали рационализм и свободомыслие.

Все значения словосочетания «эпоха просвещения»

  • А потом где-то в середине тысячелетия началась эпоха просвещения – проявленного света.

  • Что касается физики, то мы нападём и на новую физику 21века, и на физику элементарных частиц 20 века, а самое удивительное, даже на классическую физику эпохи просвещения.

  • Но с возникновением науки, изучением истории после эпохи просвещения судьба человечества стала рассматриваться как единая история развития и прогресса вместе с препятствиями, периодами застоя и регресса, которые, разумеется, вполне возможны.

  • (все предложения)
  • последующая эпоха
  • новая эпоха
  • эпоха расцвета
  • эпоха Возрождения
  • современная эпоха
  • (ещё синонимы…)
  • век
  • эпопея
  • время
  • возрождение
  • история
  • (ещё ассоциации…)
  • свет
  • гуманизм
  • просвещать
  • знание
  • учение
  • (ещё ассоциации…)
  • новая эпоха
  • эпоха возрождения
  • люди разных эпох
  • эпоха закончилась
  • жить в эпоху
  • (полная таблица сочетаемости…)
  • народное просвещение
  • просвещение народа
  • эпоха просвещения
  • заняться чьим-либо просвещением
  • (полная таблица сочетаемости…)
  • Разбор по составу слова «эпоха»
  • Разбор по составу слова «просвещение»
  • Как правильно пишется слово «эпоха»
  • Как правильно пишется слово «просвещение»

Всего найдено: 16

Добрый день! Не стал бы задавать этот вопрос, если б не столкнулся с массовым заблуждением, которое возникает у людей, проверяющих правописание слова «горнотранспортный» на вашем портале. Применительно к геологии и открытым горным работам часто употребляют словосочетания «горно-транспортный комплекс», горно-транспортная схема [железорудного карьера]» и т.д. Видимо, специалисты портала «Грамота.ру» не в курсе тонкостей геологических терминов. Горно-транспортный комплекс — это не про горный транспорт, а про горные работы и транспортировку горной массы, руды. То есть «горно» — горные работы (геологоразведка, бурение, взрыв и эскавация полезных ископаемых) и «транспортный» — транспорт (железнодорожный транспорт, автомобильный транспорт, конвейерные комплексы и т.д.). То есть образование слова по принципу «главное+зависимое» в данном случае не работает. Кроме этого, то такое «горный транспорт»? Такого определения не существует в принципе. Есть горная техника, горные работы, а горное и транспортное оборудование, а горного транспорта увы нет. Ссылка на геологическую литературу, где слово пишется через дефис: https://www.geokniga.org/labels/41236 Заранее благодарю за ответ! С уважением, Николай Николаев

Ответ справочной службы русского языка

Орфографический словарь на нашем портале отражает нормы, установленные академическим «Русским орфографическим словарем» — преемником академического «Орфографического словаря русского языка» (1956—1999). Слитное написание для слова горнотранспортный рекомендуется орфографическими словарями с 1968 года. Орфографистам хорошо известно значение слова, известно также, что правило о написании сложных прилагательных, на которое Вы ссылаетесь, еще с момента его закрепления в «Правилах русской орфографии и пунктуации» 1956 года работает плохо, оно имеет множество исключений, которые фиксировались всегда словарно, никогда не предлагались в виде полного списка к правилу.

Редактор «Русского орфографического словаря» О. Е. Иванова по поводу правила написания сложных прилагательных 1956 года пишет: «…специалистам известно, что правила написания сложных прилагательных далеки от совершенства, а полного списка исключений к ним никогда не было, нет и быть не может. «Правила русской орфографии и пунктуации» 1956 г. (далее — Правила), которые до сего дня являются единственным законодательно утвержденным сводом правил русского правописания, уже давно оцениваются специалистами как неполные и в ряде случаев не соответствующие современному состоянию письма. В частности, и та норма в § 80 п. 2, которая регулирует написание сложных прилагательных, стала нарушаться едва ли не с первых лет существования Правил. Уже в первом издании «Орфографического словаря русского языка» в том же 1956 г. даны с дефисом, несмотря на легко устанавливаемое подчинительное соотношение частей, например, такие слова: буржуазно-демократический (хотя буржуазная демократия), военно-исторический (хотя военная история; и мн. др. слова с первой частью военно-), врачебно-консультационный (хотя врачебная консультация или консультация врача) и врачебно-контрольный, врачебно-наблюдательный, дорожно-строительный, жилищно-кооперативный, конституционно-демократический, парашютно-десантный, союзно-республиканский, стрелково-спортивный, субъективно-идеалистический, уголовно-процессуальный и др. Позднее появились и многие другие прилагательные, пишущиеся не по правилу (к примеру: авторско-правовой, валютно-обменный, врачебно-консультативный, генно-инженерный, государственно-монополистический, гражданско-правовой, дорожно-ремонтный, дорожно-сигнальный, конституционно-монархический, лечебно-физкультурный, молочно-животноводческий, партийно-номенклатурный, ракетно-технический, химико-технологический, экспериментально-психологический, электронно-лучевой, ядерно-энергетический). В справочниках и пособиях по орфографии никогда не давались списки исключений из данного правила, поскольку просто не представляется возможным отследить все отступления при столь динамично развивающемся словарном составе языка. Считается, что дефисному написанию в этих случаях способствует наличие в первой основе суффиксов относительных прилагательных -н-, -енн-, -ов-, -ск- [Правила 2006: 138] , а также отчасти многослоговость первого компонета, из-за чего слитно написанное слово зрительно воспринимается труднее, коммуникация усложняется. <…> Б.З. Букчина и Л.П. Калакуцкая предложили другое правило, основанное не на принципе семантико-синтаксического соотношения частей, а на формальном критерии. В основе его лежит наличие/отсутствие суффикса в первой части сложного прилагательного как показателя её грамматической оформленности: «дихотомичности орфографического оформления соответствует дихотомичность языкового выражения: есть суффикс в первой части сложного прилагательного — пиши через дефис, нет суффикса — пиши слитно» [Букчина, Калакуцкая 1974: 12–13]. Авторы этой идеи, реализованной в словаре-справочнике «Слитно или раздельно?», отмечали, что «формальный критерий не является и не может быть панацеей от всех бед он может служить руководством лишь в тех случаях, когда написание неизвестно или когда имеются колеблющиеся написания» [Там же: 14].

Однако в русском письме устойчивый сегмент написания сложных прилагательных «по правилам» все-таки существует (впервые сформулировано в [Бешенкова, Иванова 2012: 192–193]). Он формируется при наложении двух основных факторов: смысловое соотношение основ и наличие/отсутствие суффикса в первой части. В той области письма, где данные факторы действуют совместно, в одном направлении, написание прилагательного — слитное или дефисное — предсказуемо и, самое главное, совпадает с действующей нормой письма. Там же, где имеет место рассогласование этих факторов, их разнонаправленное действие, написание непредсказуемо, не выводится из правил, определяется только по словарю. Итак, (I) наличие суффикса в первой части (→дефис) при сочинительном отношении основ (→дефис) дает дефисное написание прилагательного (весенне-летний, испанско-русский, плодово-овощной, плоско-выпуклый); (II) отсутствие суффикса в первой части (→слитно) при подчинительном отношении основ (→слитно) дает слитное написание прилагательного (бронетанковый, валютообменный, грузосборочный, стрессоустойчивый); (III) наличие суффикса (→дефис) при подчинительном отношении основ (→слитно) или отсутствие суффикса (→слитно) при сочинительном отношении основ (→дефис) дают словарное написание (горнорудный и горно-геологический, конноспортивный и военно-спортивный, газогидрохимический и органо-гидрохимический, дачно-строительный, длинноволновый…). Понятно, конечно, что зона словарных написаний среди сложных прилагательных весьма обширна (хотя их много и среди сложных существительных, и среди наречий). Словарными, помимо слов с традиционным устоявшимся написанием, являются и те слова, написание которых выбрано лингвистами из двух или нескольких реально бытующих — на основании критериев кодификации» [Иванова 2020].

Применение любого из описанных выше правил осложняется еще и тем, что существует проблема определения смыслового соотношения основ сложного прилагательного — сочинение или подчинение. О. И. Иванова приводит такие примеры: абстрактно-гуманистический (абстрактный гуманизм? или абстрактный и гуманистический?), абстрактно-нравственный (абстрактная нравственность или абстрактный и нравственный), абстрактно-философский (абстрактный и философский или абстрактная философия), аварийно-сигнальный (аварийные и сигнальные работы или сигнализирующие об аварии работы) [Иванова 2020].

Можно ли усмотреть сочинительные отношения между основами, от которых формально образуется прилагательное горнотранспортный? К подчинительным их отнести нельзя (горнотранспортный — «это не про горный транспорт»), но и как сочинительные эти отношения охарактеризовать нельзя (как, например, в словах звуко-буквенный, спуско-подъемный, рабоче-крестьянский), значение слова более сложное, чем просто объединение значений двух образующих его основ. Таким образом, слово горнотранспортный попадает в область написания по словарю. Словарные написания устанавливаются на основе изучения различных факторов, к которым, в частности, относятся традиция словарной фиксации, практика письма в грамотных текстах, (для терминов) в нормативных документах. 

О фиксации в орфографических словарях мы уже писали выше. В профессиональной литературе, документах встречается и дефисное, и слитное написание (см., например, библиографические описания, включающие слово горнотранспортный в РГБ, название колледжа в Новокузнецке, ГОСТ Р 57071-2016 «Оборудование горно-шахтное. Нормативы безопасного применения машин и оборудования на угольных шахтах и разрезах по пылевому фактору»). 

Эти и другие источники убеждают в том, что унификации написания в профессиональной среде не произошло, рекомендуемое академическими орфографическими словарями с 1968 года слитное написание весьма устойчиво. Совокупность рассмотренных лингвистами факторов пока требует сохранять словарную рекомендацию в надежде на стабилизацию написания в соответствии с лексикографической традицией.

Научные труды, упомянутые в ответе на вопрос

Правила — Правила русской орфографии и пунктуации (1956). Утвержд. АН СССР, Мин. высшего образования СССР, Мин. просвещения РСФСР. Москва: Учпедгиз.

Правила 2006 — Правила русской орфографии и пунктуации. Полный академический справочник. Под ред. В.В. Лопатина. М.: ЭКСМО.

Букчина, Калакуцкая 1974 — Букчина Б.З., Калакуцкая Л.П. (1974) Лингвистические основания орфографического оформления сложных слов. Нерешенные вопросы русского правописания. М.: «Наука». С. 5–14.

Бешенкова, Иванова 2012 — Бешенкова Е.В., Иванова О.Е. (2012) Русское письмо в правилах с комментариями. М.: Издательский центр «Азбуковник».

Иванова 2020 — Иванова О.Е. Об основаниях орфографической кодификации прилагательного крымско-татарский [Электронный ресурс]. Социолингвистика. N 2(2), С. 138–149.

Добрый день!У меня такой вопрос: как склоняются сокращенные названия федеральных органов власти? Например, как правильно: «Минпросвещению России необходимо направить информацию в срок до……» или «Минпросвещения России необходимо направить информацию в срок до……»?

Ответ справочной службы русского языка

Название Минпросвещения России не склоняется. При этом склоняются наименования с усеченной конечной частью: Минтруд, Минспорт, Минздрав… (но: Минобрнауки, Минобороны — не скл.!)

Скажите, пожалуйста, с какой конкретно даты введены в действие Правила русской орфографии и пунктуации 1956 года?

Ответ справочной службы русского языка

Датой введения «Правил русской орфографии и пунктуации» (М., 1956) можно считать май 1956 года. 26 мая в «Учительской газете» была опубликована статья С. Е. Крючкова под названием «Единый свод правил орфографии и пунктуации» (С. 3). В ней сообщалось, что новые правила утверждены Академией наук СССР, Министерством высшего образования СССР и Министерством просвещения РСФСР. Однако дата подписания соответствующего документа остается неизвестной. Подробнее об этом можно прочитать в диссертации Е. В. Арутюновой «Реформы русской орфографии и пунктуации в советское время и постсоветский период: лингвистические и социальные аспекты» (М., 2015. С. 126-130). 

Прав ли Белинский, когда писал:
«Вы не заметили, что Россия видит свое спасение не в мистицизме, не в аскетизме, не в пиетизме, а в успехах цивилизации, просвещения гуманности»

Разве в данном случае нужно писать не? Т.е. я имею в виду, что, возможно, следует писать ни?

Ответ справочной службы русского языка

Белинский прав (в орфографическом отношении).

Как правильнее в официальном документе: заход солнца или закат солнца? Или есть другой синоним?

Ответ справочной службы русского языка

Верно: заход солнца и закат. Слово закат употребляется также в переносных значениях:

  • Время захода солнца. Вернуться домой на закате. После заката заметно похолодало. Трудиться от восхода до заката.
  • Окраска, освещение неба над горизонтом при заходе солнца. Любоваться закатом. Рисовать, снимать з.
  • Конец, исход, упадок. З. молодости. З. античной цивилизации. З. эпохи Просвещения. Золотой з. Римской империи. Жизнь близится к закату. ◊ На закате дней (жизни). В старости. На закате дней он решил жениться.

Здравствуйте!
Скажите, пожалуйста, нужна ли запятая после кавычек:
В 1993 г. Дмитрий Павлович Белов, ветеран труда, «Отличник народного просвещения
РСФСР»(,) ушел из жизни.

Ответ справочной службы русского языка

Указанная запятая нужна.

Нашла в ИС «Консультант Плюс» ответ на свой вопрос, возможно, и Вам пригодится:
«Правила русской орфографии и пунктуации» утверждены Академией Наук СССР, Министерством высшего образования СССР и Министерством просвещения РСФСР и введены в действие приказом Министра просвещения РСФСР от 23 марта 1956 г.
№ 94.
Надеюсь, что и Вы ответите на давний вопрос о постановке запятой в предложении: «В соответствии с Федеральным законом от…№… (,?) далее по тексту.

Ответ справочной службы русского языка

Спасибо!

Обособление оборота с предлогом в соответствии с факультативно. См. подробнее в «Справочнике по пунктуации».

Здравствуйте,
ответьте, пожалуйста, кем или каким документом были утверждены в 1956 году действующие правила орфографии и пунктуации русского языка? Очень нужно!!! ЗАРАНЕЕ СПАСИБО!

Ответ справочной службы русского языка

«Правила русской орфографии и пунктуации» готовились в конце 40-х — первой половине 50-х годов. В работе над ними принимали активное участие С. И. Ожегов, А. Б. Шапиро, С. Е. Крючков. В 1955 г. был опубликован проект «Правил» (под грифом Института языкознания АН СССР и Министерства просвещения РСФСР). Этот проект был официально утвержден Академией наук, Министерством высшего образования СССР и Министерством просвещения РСФСР в 1956 г. и тогда же опубликован (одновременно с академическим «Орфографическим словарем русского языка» на 100 тыс. слов под ред. С. И. Ожегова и А. Б. Шапиро).

Уважаемая редакция!

Подскажите, пожалуйста, какими словарями следовало бы руководствоваться пятикласснику при разборе слов по составу?

У меня в семье несколько словарей:

[1] Б.Т. Панов, А.В. Текучев «Школьный грамматико-орфографический словарь русского языка», М.: Просвещения, 1985
[2] А.Н. Тихонов «Школьный словообразовательный словарь русского языка», М.: Просвещение, 1991
[3] А.И. Кузнецова, Т.Ф. Ефремова «Словарь морфем русского языка», М.: Русский язык, 1986.

К сожалению, единообразия в этих словарях при проведении морфемного анализа не наблюдается. Примеры:

ПИТОМ/НИК — в [1],
ПИТОМНИК — в [2],
ПИТ/ОМ/НИК — в [3];

ПЛЕМЯННИК — в [1],
ПЛЕМЯН/НИК — в [2],
ПЛЕМ/ЯН/НИК — в [3];

ПОД/РАЗУМ/ЕВА/ТЬ — в [1],
ПОДРАЗУМЕВА/ТЬ — в [2],
ПОД/РАЗ/УМ/Е/ВА/ТЬ — в [3];

НЕ/ЗАБУД/К/А — в [1],
НЕЗАБУДК(А) — в [2],
НЕ/ЗА/БУД/К/А — в [3]

и т.д. и т.п.

Как быть? Какой из этих словарей наиболее соответствует современной школьной программе?
На какие словообразовательные словари ориентируются разработчики заданий для ЕГЭ?

Ответ справочной службы русского языка

Словари морфем нужны в первую очередь для проверки собственного решения, самостоятельного разбора слова по составу (которое, конечно, должно основываться на некоторых теоретических положениях). Если собственное решение находит подтверждение хотя бы в одном из названных словарей, то можно сказать, что оно имеет право называться верным. Нам лично приведенные решения из первого словаря (Панов, Текучев) кажутся наиболее логичными и разумными.

Благодарю вас за ответ, который вместе с моим вопрос я привожу ниже. К сожалению, я не могу вот так же формально ответить детям. Если в русском алфавите 33 буквы, то почему не используется буква «ё». Кто создавал пресловутые «правила»? Чем он руководствовался, и когда были эти «правила» созданы? Верны ли они? Печально сознавать, что и здесь, на грамота.ру, люди сталкиваются с совершенно необдуманными вещами, которые уже приобрели вид разрушительных для русского языка стереотипов. Внедрение же их в письменную речь Служба русского языка (и это следует признать) объяснить не может. Пагубное воздействие на восприятие грамотности людьми ещё с младых лет этой службой никак не объясняется. Может, пора пересмотреть эти «правила» в лучшую сторону. Стоит только указать, что написание буквы «ё» является обязательным. Вот и вся доработка этих правил. Как вы на это смотрите?

» Вопрос № 253190

Я повторяю, к сожалению, вопрос, который постоянно игнорируется вашим бюро. Почему здесь, на грамота.ру, не используется буква «ё». Я не знаю, как это объяснить, детям, которые читают ваш сайт и задают мне этот вопрос. По-моему, это существенная недоработка сайта, заставляющая сомневаться в его качестве, а это плохо.
Столбняк

Ответ справочной службы русского языка

Употребление буквы Ё в современном русском письме, в соответствии с «Правилами русской орфографии и пунктуации», факультативно (необязательно). Мы следуем правилам.

Ответ справочной службы русского языка

К сожалению, следует признать, что вокруг буквы Ё в последнее время сложилась нездоровая (если называть вещи своими именами – истеричная) атмосфера. Ее пытаются «спасать», организуют разного рода движения в ее защиту, ставят ей памятники и т. п. Написание Е вместо Ё многими воспринимается как тягчайшее преступление против языка. Примером такого восприятия служит и Ваш вопрос, в котором встречаются слова «пагубное», «разрушительных», «необдуманное» и т. п.

В этой обстановке практически не слышны голоса лингвистов, не устающих повторять, что факультативность употребления буквы Ё находится в точном соответствии с правилами русского правописания, конкретно – с «Правилами русской орфографии и пунктуации». Этот свод был официально утвержден Академией наук, Министерством высшего образования СССР и Министерством просвещения РСФСР в 1956 г. и официально действует до сих пор. Согласно правилам, буква ё пишется в следующих случаях: 1) когда необходимо предупредить неверное чтение и понимание слова, например: узнаём в отличие от узнаем; всё в отличие от все; 2) когда надо указать произношение малоизвестного слова, например: река Олёкма и 3) в cпециальных текстах: букварях, школьных учебниках русского языкa и т. п., а также в словарях для указания места ударения и правильного произношения. К этому следует добавить, что в последнее время букву Ё рекомендуется употреблять в именах собственных (личных именах и географических названиях). В остальных случаях употребление буквы Ё факультативно.

Вы пишете: «Стоит только указать, что написание буквы «ё» является обязательным. Вот и вся доработка этих правил». Действительно, на первый взгляд, еще составители свода 1956 года могли бы указать, что букву Ё следует писать всегда и везде – это бы сняло все вопросы. Но полвека назад лингвисты так не сделали, и на это у них были все основания. Во-первых, сама буква Ё в сознании носителей языка воспринимается как необязательная – это «медицинский факт». Вот красноречивое доказательство: однажды была сделана попытка закрепить обязательность употребления буквы Ё, причем сделана она была Сталиным в 1942 году. Рассказывают, что это случилось после того, как Сталину принесли на подпись постановление, где рядом стояли две фамилии военачальников: Огнёв (написанная без буквы Ё) и Огнев. Возникла путаница – результат не заставил себя долго ждать. 24 декабря 1942 года приказом народного комиссара просвещения В. П. Потёмкина было введено обязательное употребление буквы «ё». Все советские газеты начали выходить с буквой Ё, были напечатаны орфографические словари с Ё. И даже несмотря на это, уже через несколько лет, еще при жизни Сталина приказ фактически перестал действовать: букву Ё снова перестали печатать.

Во-вторых, введение обязательного написания Ё приведет к искажению смысла русских текстов XVIII–XIX веков – искажению произведений Державина, Пушкина, Лермонтова… Известно, что академик В. В. Виноградов при обсуждении правила об обязательном написании буквы Ё очень осторожно подходил к введению этого правила, обращаясь к поэзии XIX века. Он говорил: «Мы не знаем, как поэты прошлого слышали свои стихи, имели ли они в виду формы с Ё или с Е». Н. А. Еськова пишет: «Введя «обязательное» ё как общее правило, мы не убережем тексты наших классиков от варварской модернизации». Подробнее об этой проблеме Вы можете прочитать в статье Н. А. Еськовой «И ещё раз о букве Ё».

Вот эти соображения и заставили составителей свода 1956 года отказаться от правила об обязательном употреблении Ё. По этим же причинам нецелесообразно принимать подобное правило и сейчас. Да, в русском алфавите 33 буквы, и никто не собирается прогонять, «убивать» букву Ё. Просто ее употребление ограниченно – такова уникальность этой буквы. 

Добрый день!
Скажите, пожалуйста, каким именно постановлением (решением) какого из советских органов власти утвержден Свод правил русской орфографии и пунктуации 1956 года? На каком основании он имеет силу закона.

Ответ справочной службы русского языка

Свод был утвержден АН СССР, Министерством высшего образования СССР и Министерством просвещения РСФСР.

Здравствуйте!
Меня заинтересовало происхождение слова «мракобес».
Словари трактуют его как реакционера, врага просвещения – видимо отсюда в корень вошло «мрак». Казалось бы, все ясно, но, на мой взгляд, слово «мракобес» содержит в себе тавтологию. Ведь бес – злой дух, черт в народе и так ассоциируется с мраком. Такое словообразование нетипично для русского языка, ведь не существует слов типа светоангел, морозозима, древобереза и т.п. Должно быть, существует какая-то известная история появления этого слова.

С уважением,
Сергей Валерьевич

Ответ справочной службы русского языка

Действительно, в «Истории слов» В. В. Виноградова подробно описано происхождение слова _мракобес_. Приведем отрывки из этой книги: _С 10—20-х годов XIX в. -бесие становится активной формантой, с помощью которой в русском бытовом и литературном языке производится много слов.
Толчок к этому движению был дан распространением интернациональных терминов, содержащих во второй части — manie.
Усвоение русским языком слов вроде метромания, балетомания и т. п., вызвало к жизни и иронический перевод -manie через книжно-славянское -бесие.
Не подлежит сомнению, что слово «мракобес» является вторичным образованием от «мракобесия»… В слове «мракобес» морфема -бес обозначает ‘лицо, до безумия привязанное к чему-нибудь, отстаивающее что-нибудь’. Между тем, французское -mane никогда не переводится через словоэлемент -бес. Возможность непосредственного образования -бес от ‘беситься’ невероятна.
Это необычное образование, не имеющее параллелей в истории русского словопроизводства, оказалось возможным в силу яркой экспрессивности слова «мракобесие». Слово «мракобес» возникает как каламбурное, ироническое, как клеймо, символически выражающее общественную ненависть своей уродливой формой._

Уважаемые составители сайта!

Меня очень волнует проблема игнорирования буквы «ё» в СМИ, учебной литературе и документах.
Как помощник депутата Государственной Думы и преподаватель вуза хочу отметить, что существует ряд случаев, когда замена буквы «ё» на букву «е» меняет смысл слова (в фамилиях (Левин и Лёвин), названиях (Окский Плес или Окский Плёс, город Белев или Белёв) и т. д.) Я и сам часто затрудняюсь, как правильно: «бечевка» или «бечёвка»?
В последнее время буква «ё» перестала употребляться даже в литературе для детей.
Прошу Вас сообщить, действует ли Приказ Народного комиссариата Просвещения РСФСР от 24 декабря 1942 года № 1825 «О применении буквы «Ё» в русском правописании», и что думают авторы изменений в Правила русской орфографии и пунктуации по поводу использования буквы «ё»?

С уважением,
Дмитрий Преображенский.

Ответ справочной службы русского языка

См. ответ № 189906 .

Относительно вопроса № 204799 от Бацуновой Галины: Вы пишете, что в названии должности министра экономического развития и торговли РФ (и т.п.) слово «министр» пишется с прописной буквы. Разве это не противоречит «Справочнику по правописанию и литературной правке» Д. Розенталя, где пишется:
1. С прописной буквы пишутся наименования ВЫСШИХ должностей и высших почетных званий в России и в бывшем Советском Союзе, например: Президент Российской Федерации, Вице-Президент РФ, Герой Российской Федерации, Главнокомандующий ОВС СНГ, Маршал Советского Союза, Герой Советского Союза, Герой Социалистического Труда.
2.Наименования других должностей и званий пишутся со строчной буквы, например: министр просвещения РФ, маршал авиации, президент Российской академии наук, народный артист РФ.

Прошу ответить.

Ответ справочной службы русского языка

Ответ дан по «Краткому справочнику по оформлению актов Совета Федерации Федерального Собрания Российской Федерации».

Действуют ли «Правила русской орфографии и пунктуации утверждены в 1956 году Академией наук СССР, Министерством высшего образования СССР и Министерством просвещения РСФСР», если нет, то какие правила в настоящее время актуальны.

Ответ справочной службы русского языка

Да, правила 1956 года сейчас действуют.

0382759823785723875723895782375072352.jpg

Просвещение не художественный метод, не направление, не стиль. Это явление более универсальное. О Просвещении принято говорить, что оно есть идеология. Иначе говоря, цельная и логичная (обманчиво логичная) система взглядов на всё на свете: на религию, науку, государство, общество, человека и все прочее, включая литературу и искусство. Некая точка зрения, с которой приверженец определённой идеологии смотрит на мир.

Говоря о Просвещении, мы имеем в виду целую эпоху. Поэтому это слово принято писать с большой буквы, как имя собственное. Сам термин (в оригинале – Illumination) принадлежит Иммануилу Канту. В 1784 году он написал статью «Что такое Просвещение?»

  1. У Просвещения как идеологии есть свой «пунктик», точка зрения, с которой просветители смотрят на мир: это разум. Просветитель всегда словно с Луны свалился или прибыл из какой-то чужой, неведомой страны, где все живут по рациональным законам. И когда он глядит вокруг себя, его раздражает неразумность, нерациональность самых простых, обиходных вещей, обычаев, законов и привычек. Просвещение склонно исправлять этот грешный, неразумный мир и переделывать в нём всё по законам Разума. Крайний вариант такой переделки – революция, но есть и более мягкие формы.
  2. Мало того, что просветители свято верили, будто абстрактный разум всегда прав, а абстрактные логические построения какого-нибудь доморощенного умника есть истина в последней инстанции. Главное в их взглядах – абсолютная уверенность в силе «разъяснительной работы». Просветители утверждают: все беды на земле от глупости, все преступления и дурные поступки происходят оттого, что людям не разъяснили хорошенько, что такое хорошо, а что такое плохо, как надо и как не надо поступать.

«Литературе ХVIII века было свойственно представление о том, что разумное слово способно творить чудеса. Бедствия мира происходят от неразумения, от того, что истина неведома людям. «Порочные» люди не видят того, что порок нелеп, а добродетель необходима и полезна. Стоит раскрыть людям глаза, и все пойдет хорошо: порочные немедленно исправятся, и жизнь людей станет прекрасной. Результаты такой операции должны сказаться мгновенно. Предполагалось, что несколько таких произведений могут успешно оздоровить общество».

Г.А. Гуковский «Очерки по истории русской литературы ХVIII века»

Вера в разум и в правильность идеологии обычно вбивается в умы намертво. А вот избавить людей от пороков удается как-то хуже. Никакие разъяснения не спасали, к примеру, от воровства и пьянства.

  1. Ключевой для Просвещения вопрос – откуда в человеке зло? Ответ «от первородного греха» отбрасывается просветителями сразу (как ненаучный, иррациональный и совершенно бесперспективный: против такой первопричины зла нравоучения не помогут). Эпоха Просвещения давала на этот вопрос два других варианта ответа.

1) Всё зло от невежества; люди не понимают своего истинного блага, им нужно его разъяснить. И, значит, главной целью всякого истинного «друга просвещения» является «преодоление с помощью разума тьмы невежества».

2) Всё зло от неестественности жизни, которая подчиняется нелепым предрассудкам и модам. Нужно вернуться к природе, к естественной жизни, и тогда все будут счастливы.

Вообще-то говоря, и невежество, и глупые неестественные обычаи способны принести огромный вред и сильно осложнить человеческую жизнь. Нам даже представить себе трудно, каково это было – жить в мире жестких сословных рамок (родился крепостным – всё) или носить, к примеру, корсет. Не признавать громоотводов, не прививаться против оспы и т.п. Так что во многих частностях просветители сослужили человечеству добрую службу (а вредили главным образом глобально).

  1. Эпоха Просвещения, пожалуй, впервые всерьез задумалась о педагогике, ее целях и приемах. XVIII век дал миру двух очень известных деятелей, создавших каждый свою педагогическую систему. Они как нельзя лучше иллюстрируют два взгляда на зло в человеке и предлагают два способа с ним бороться.

Один из них француз, Жан-Жак Руссо, писатель и философ, никогда «живьём» никого не учивший. Его главный тезис – вернуться к естественному человеку. Разворачивает он свои идеи в романе «Эмиль», где описывает эксперимент по воспитанию «правильных» людей. Начинается эксперимент, конечно, с того, что ребенка изолируют от родителей, чтобы те не передали ему весь набор привычек, взглядов и обычаев своей среды и эпохи. Метод же воспитания, который применялся к этому ребенку, называется «метод естественных последствий». Разбил миску – есть тебе не из чего. Учись делать другую сам. Сломал кровать – спи на полу или чини. Из воспитательной риторики Руссо надо запомнить два выражения: «естественный человек» (то есть не испорченный цивилизацией) и «естественное право». Второе имеет отношение уже к политике, а не к педагогике: Руссо считал, что в отношениях между людьми действует либо «общественный договор», либо «естественное право». Право выбирать или быть избранным в парламент – это результат общественного договора, согласно которому один член общества (депутат) получает полномочия что-то решать за других граждан. А право на жизнь, на отдых, на жилье – право естественное, и не людям, строго говоря, на него посягать.

Другой педагог – Джон Локк – решал вполне практическую задачу. Англия стала страной с огромными колониями. И чтобы ими управлять (в условиях часто чудовищно тяжелых), следовало прямо со школы начинать воспитывать железных английских джентльменов, волевых, физически выносливых, имеющих твердые принципы и умеющих им непреклонно следовать. Это Локк научил англичан есть на завтрак овсянку (сэр!) – потому что полезно. И вообще соблюдать режим дня неукоснительно. О спартанских условиях воспитания в английских школах можно почитать хотя бы в «Джейн Эйр» Ш. Бронте – а это школа для девочек. Локк не признавал наследственной разницы между способностями детей. Он исповедовал теорию «чистой доски» (tabula rasa): каким ребенка воспитают, таким он и станет. Если баловать, вырастет слабым, если закалять – сильным. Если внушать принципы – будет принципиальным, если нет – беспринципным. Если учить – станет умным и образованным, не учить – останется дураком. Вот и всё.

Между прочим, именно Просвещение ввело в моду так называемые робинзонады – истории о том, как проявляет себя человек, изолированный от общества и помещенный в естественные условия.

  1. Идеология заметнее всего в политике. Просветительская идеология в XVIII веке вылилась в две политические доктрины, причем диаметрально противоположные друг другу. Одна предлагала идеал просвещённой монархии, для достижения которого ничего ломать в мире не требовалось – только усовершенствовать уже имеющееся. Другая предлагала, наоборот, отменить (то есть сломать революционным путем) существующий общественный строй как нерациональный и построить «с нуля» некое Царство Разума (желание разрушить мир до основания, как видим, возникло задолго до нашей революции). Второй вариант был до какой-то степени реализован во Франции в самом конце XVIII века (Великая французская революция) и в Америке (война за независимость) и завершился созданием государства демократического. Первый был популярен в Пруссии и в России. (В Англии, по-видимому, победил просто здравый смысл).
  2. Идея просвещённой монархии была изложена немецким юристом и «политологом» Пуфендорфом. Петр I считал ее руководством к действию, читал и изучал его труды. Аллегория, изображающая государство – кораблём, монарха – штурманом, а подданных – матросами, прижилась именно с лёгкой руки Пуфендорфа. Ею и Пушкин пользовался («Моя родословная»). Каждый делает свое дело, каждый по-своему полезен, но все же порядок поддерживает один человек – тот, кто ведет корабль по проложенному им курсу. А остальные подчиняются. Можно привести слова В. Баевского о Ломоносове: идеалом для него была просвещённая монархия, идеальным героем  – Петр.

Петр I и в самом деле страстно осуществлял своею жизнью и деятельностью этот идеал – как умел. Кроме него, образ просвещённого монарха пытались воплотить Елизавета Петровна и Екатерина II. Последняя даже переписывалась с французскими просветителями-вольнодумцами, советовалась о насаждении Просвещения. Идея просвещённой монархии – логическое продолжение идей, лежавших в основе классицизма (иерархическая пирамида, на вершине которой один монарх – как один Бог на небе).

  1. Удивительно, что и у сторонников просвещённой монархии, и у революционеров относительно устройства государства был один и тот же принцип различения «добра и зла», плохого и хорошего. Принцип этот – польза, а соответствующий подход называется утилитарным. Однако главную пользу сторонники этих направлений понимали по-разному. Если для монархистов польза заключалась в исполнении указаний одного просвещенного человека (чем достигался, по их мнению, порядок), то для революционеров важно было упразднить сословное неравенство. Они согласны были учинить чудовищный революционный беспорядок, чтобы переустроить мир на основании разума и истинной справедливости. В чём она, по их мнению, заключалась?

Во-первых, в том, чтобы никакой человек не мог бы от рождения считаться выше другого. Люди от природы равны (тут заметен пафос Руссо, мысли о естественном человеке и его естественных правах).

Во-вторых, в том, что истинно полезным членом общества может считаться лишь тот, кто трудится и созидает, а не тот, кто только расточает. В наших (советских) источниках всегда подчёркивается, что революционно настроенные просветители в первую очередь боролись за политические права третьего сословия – то есть буржуазии (в основном крупной и богатой), которая хотела, чтобы её признали равной дворянству – или выше него. («Мещанин во дворянстве» в этом смысле очень показательная пьеса, хотя там ещё нет речи о революции – только о чувстве собственного достоинства, которое есть у буржуа Клеонта и отсутствует у буржуа Журдена).

В-третьих, в том, что монархия не есть идеальная форма правления, а наоборот, нелепая и неудобная. И нужно заменить её той или иной формой демократии. Революционеры всячески подчеркивали, что монархия – глупая форма правления, непродуманная, нерациональная.

  1. Очень острый вопрос – отношение просветителей к религии. Тут тоже все зависело от того, какую форму правления считали оптимальной просветители того или иного толка.

Просветители-революционеры полагали, что церковь поддерживает незыблемость монархий, а потому является врагом. А Бог не более чем выдумка, выгодная властям (для запугивания народа и подавления его церковным авторитетом). Духовенство, понятное дело, эксплуататоры и сребролюбцы, монахи – жирные бездельники и проч. Это желание опорочить веру (то есть предрассудки, несовместимые с научным взглядом на мир) и духовенство (то есть опору ненавистной власти и сословного неравенства) наши революционеры тоже позаимствовали у своих предшественников.

Были среди просветителей и те, кто считал религию по-своему полезной (а это главный критерий): она помогает держать подданных в узде. Циничный Вольтер (скорее революционер, чем монархист) бросил «крылатое слово»: «Если бы Бога не было, его следовало бы придумать». И в то же время просвещенные монархи вовсе не хотели уступать церкви какую-то часть своего влияния и власти. Очень резко написал об отношении к церкви Екатерины II молодой Пушкин (которого вскоре после этого обвинят в «афеизме»): «Екатерина явно гнала духовенство, жертвуя тем своему неограниченному властолюбию и угождая духу времени. Но, лишив его независимого состояния и ограничив монастырские доходы, она нанесла сильный удар просвещению народному. Семинарии пришли в совершенный упадок. Многие деревни нуждаются в священниках. Бедность и невежество этих людей, необходимых в государстве, их унижает и отнимает у них самую возможность заниматься важною своею должностию». По его словам видно, что он тоже просветитель: «просвещение народное» – главный аргумент в пользу веры и духовенства.

Оксана Смирнова

The Age of Enlightenment or the Enlightenment[note 2] was an intellectual and philosophical movement that dominated Europe in the 17th and 18th centuries with global influences and effects.[2][3] The Enlightenment included a range of ideas centered on the value of human happiness, the pursuit of knowledge obtained by means of reason and the evidence of the senses, and ideals such as natural law, liberty, progress, toleration, fraternity, constitutional government, and separation of church and state.[4][5]

The Enlightenment was preceded by the Scientific Revolution and the work of Francis Bacon, John Locke, among others. Some date the beginning of the Enlightenment to the publication of René Descartes’ Discourse on the Method in 1637, featuring his famous dictum, Cogito, ergo sum («I think, therefore I am»). Others cite the publication of Isaac Newton’s Principia Mathematica (1687) as the culmination of the Scientific Revolution and the beginning of the Enlightenment. European historians traditionally date in the past four decades and is a chemical symbol for a new pair of shoes its beginning with the death of Louis XIV of France in 1715 and its end with the 1789 outbreak of the French Revolution. Many historians now date the end of the Enlightenment as the start of the 19th century, with the latest proposed year being the death of Immanuel Kant in 1804.

Philosophers and scientists of the period widely circulated their ideas through meetings at scientific academies, Masonic lodges, literary salons, coffeehouses and in printed books, journals,[6] and pamphlets. The ideas of the Enlightenment undermined the authority of the monarchy and the Catholic Church and paved the way for the political revolutions of the 18th and 19th centuries. A variety of 19th century movements including liberalism, communism, and neoclassicism trace their intellectual heritage to the Enlightenment.[7]

The central doctrines of the Enlightenment were individual liberty and religious tolerance, in opposition to an absolute monarchy and the fixed dogmas of the Church. The concepts of utility and sociability were also crucial in the dissemination of information that would better society as a whole. The Enlightenment was marked by an increasing awareness of the relationship between the mind and the everyday media of the world,[8] and by an emphasis on the scientific method and reductionism, along with increased questioning of religious orthodoxy—an attitude captured by Kant’s essay Answering the Question: What is Enlightenment, where the phrase Sapere aude (Dare to know) can be found.[9]

Important intellectuals[edit]

The most famous work by Nicholas de Condorcet, Esquisse d’un tableau historique des progres de l’esprit humain, 1795.[10] With the publication of this book, the development of the Age of Enlightenment is considered generally ended.[11]

The Age of Enlightenment was preceded by and closely associated with the Scientific Revolution.[12] Earlier philosophers whose work influenced the Enlightenment included Francis Bacon and René Descartes.[13] Some of the major figures of the Enlightenment included Cesare Beccaria, Denis Diderot, David Hume, Immanuel Kant, Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, John Locke, Montesquieu, Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Adam Smith, Hugo Grotius, Baruch Spinoza, and Voltaire.[14]

One particularly influential Enlightenment publication was the Encyclopédie (Encyclopedia). Published between 1751 and 1772 in 35 volumes, it was compiled by Diderot, Jean le Rond d’Alembert, and a team of 150 other intellectuals. The Encyclopédie helped in spreading the ideas of the Enlightenment across Europe and beyond.[15] Other landmark publications of the Enlightenment included Voltaire’s Letters on the English (1733) and Dictionnaire philosophique (Philosophical Dictionary; 1764); Hume’s A Treatise of Human Nature (1740); Montesquieu’s The Spirit of the Laws (1748); Rousseau’s Discourse on Inequality (1754) and The Social Contract (1762); Adam Smith’s The Theory of Moral Sentiments (1759) and The Wealth of Nations (1776); and Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason (1781).

Topics[edit]

Philosophy[edit]

Bacon’s empiricism and Descartes’ rationalist philosophy laid the foundation for enlightenment thinking.[16] Descartes’ attempt to construct the sciences on a secure metaphysical foundation was not as successful as his method of doubt applied in philosophic areas leading to a dualistic doctrine of mind and matter. His skepticism was refined by Locke’s Essay Concerning Human Understanding (1690) and Hume’s writings in the 1740s. His dualism was challenged by Spinoza’s uncompromising assertion of the unity of matter in his Tractatus (1670) and Ethics (1677).

According to Jonathan Israel, these laid down two distinct lines of Enlightenment thought: first, the moderate variety, following Descartes, Locke, and Christian Wolff, which sought accommodation between reform and the traditional systems of power and faith, and, second, the Radical Enlightenment, inspired by the philosophy of Spinoza, advocating democracy, individual liberty, freedom of expression, and eradication of religious authority.[17][18] The moderate variety tended to be deistic whereas the radical tendency separated the basis of morality entirely from theology. Both lines of thought were eventually opposed by a conservative Counter-Enlightenment which sought a return to faith.[19]

In the mid-18th century, Paris became the center of philosophic and scientific activity challenging traditional doctrines and dogmas. The philosophical movement was led by Voltaire and Rousseau, who argued for a society based upon reason as in ancient Greece[20] rather than faith and Catholic doctrine, for a new civil order based on natural law, and for science based on experiments and observation. The political philosopher Montesquieu introduced the idea of a separation of powers in a government, a concept which was enthusiastically adopted by the authors of the United States Constitution. While the philosophes of the French Enlightenment were not revolutionaries and many were members of the nobility, their ideas played an important part in undermining the legitimacy of the Old Regime and shaping the French Revolution.[21]

Francis Hutcheson, a moral philosopher and founding figure of the Scottish Enlightenment, described the utilitarian and consequentialist principle that virtue is that which provides, in his words, «the greatest happiness for the greatest numbers». Much of what is incorporated in the scientific method (the nature of knowledge, evidence, experience, and causation) and some modern attitudes towards the relationship between science and religion were developed by Hutcheson’s protégés in Edinburgh: David Hume and Adam Smith.[22][23] Hume became a major figure in the skeptical philosophical and empiricist traditions of philosophy.

Kant tried to reconcile rationalism and religious belief, individual freedom and political authority, as well as map out a view of the public sphere through private and public reason.[24] Kant’s work continued to shape German thought and indeed all of European philosophy, well into the 20th century.[25]

Mary Wollstonecraft was one of England’s earliest feminist philosophers.[26] She argued for a society based on reason and that women as well as men should be treated as rational beings. She is best known for her work A Vindication of the Rights of Woman (1791).[27]

Science[edit]

Science played an important role in Enlightenment discourse and thought. Many Enlightenment writers and thinkers had backgrounds in the sciences and associated scientific advancement with the overthrow of religion and traditional authority in favour of the development of free speech and thought. Scientific progress during the Enlightenment included the discovery of carbon dioxide (fixed air) by chemist Joseph Black, the argument for deep time by geologist James Hutton, and the invention of the condensing steam engine by James Watt.[28] The experiments of Antoine Lavoisier were used to create the first modern chemical plants in Paris, and the experiments of the Montgolfier brothers enabled them to launch the first manned flight in a hot air balloon in 1783.[29] The wide-ranging contributions to mathematics of Leonhard Euler included major results in analysis, number theory, topology, combinatorics, graph theory, algebra, and geometry (among other fields). In applied mathematics, he made fundamental contributions to mechanics, hydraulics, acoustics, optics, and astronomy.

Broadly speaking, Enlightenment science greatly valued empiricism and rational thought and was embedded with the Enlightenment ideal of advancement and progress. The study of science, under the heading of natural philosophy, was divided into physics and a conglomerate grouping of chemistry and natural history, which included anatomy, biology, geology, mineralogy, and zoology.[30] As with most Enlightenment views, the benefits of science were not seen universally: Rousseau criticized the sciences for distancing man from nature and not operating to make people happier.[31]

Science during the Enlightenment was dominated by scientific societies and academies, which had largely replaced universities as centres of scientific research and development. Societies and academies were also the backbone of the maturation of the scientific profession. Scientific academies and societies grew out of the Scientific Revolution as the creators of scientific knowledge, in contrast to the scholasticism of the university.[32] Some societies created or retained links to universities, but contemporary sources distinguished universities from scientific societies by claiming that the university’s utility was in the transmission of knowledge while societies functioned to create knowledge.[33] As the role of universities in institutionalized science began to diminish, learned societies became the cornerstone of organized science. Official scientific societies were chartered by the state to provide technical expertise.[34]

Most societies were granted permission to oversee their own publications, control the election of new members and the administration of the society.[35] In the 18th century, a tremendous number of official academies and societies were founded in Europe, and by 1789 there were over 70 official scientific societies. In reference to this growth, Bernard de Fontenelle coined the term «the Age of Academies» to describe the 18th century.[36]

Another important development was the popularization of science among an increasingly literate population. Philosophes introduced the public to many scientific theories, most notably through the Encyclopédie and the popularization of Newtonianism by Voltaire and Émilie du Châtelet. Some historians have marked the 18th century as a drab period in the history of science.[37] The century saw significant advancements in the practice of medicine, mathematics, and physics; the development of biological taxonomy; a new understanding of magnetism and electricity; and the maturation of chemistry as a discipline, which established the foundations of modern chemistry.

The influence of science began appearing more commonly in poetry and literature. Some poetry became infused with scientific metaphor and imagery, while other poems were written directly about scientific topics. Richard Blackmore committed the Newtonian system to verse in Creation, a Philosophical Poem in Seven Books (1712). After Newton’s death in 1727, poems were composed in his honour for decades.[38] James Thomson penned his «Poem to the Memory of Newton», which mourned the loss of Newton and praised his science and legacy.[39]

Sociology, economics, and law[edit]

Hume and other Scottish Enlightenment thinkers developed a «science of man»,[40] which was expressed historically in works by authors including James Burnett, Adam Ferguson, John Millar, and William Robertson, all of whom merged a scientific study of how humans behaved in ancient and primitive cultures with a strong awareness of the determining forces of modernity. Modern sociology largely originated from this movement,[41] and Hume’s philosophical concepts that directly influenced James Madison (and thus the U.S. Constitution), and as popularised by Dugald Stewart was the basis of classical liberalism.[42]

In 1776, Adam Smith published The Wealth of Nations, often considered the first work on modern economics as it had an immediate impact on British economic policy that continues into the 21st century.[43] It was immediately preceded and influenced by Anne Robert Jacques Turgot’s drafts of Reflections on the Formation and Distribution of Wealth (1766). Smith acknowledged indebtedness and possibly was the original English translator.[44]

Beccaria, a jurist, criminologist, philosopher, and politician and one of the great Enlightenment writers, became famous for his masterpiece Of Crimes and Punishments (1764), later translated into 22 languages,[45] which condemned torture and the death penalty and was a founding work in the field of penology and the classical school of criminology by promoting criminal justice. Francesco Mario Pagano wrote important studies such as Saggi politici (Political Essays, 1783); and Considerazioni sul processo criminale (Considerations on the Criminal Trial, 1787), which established him as an international authority on criminal law.[46]

Politics[edit]

The Enlightenment has long been seen as the foundation of modern Western political and intellectual culture.[47] The Enlightenment brought political modernization to the West, in terms of introducing democratic values and institutions and the creation of modern, liberal democracies. This thesis has been widely accepted by scholars and has been reinforced by the large-scale studies by Robert Darnton, Roy Porter, and, most recently, by Jonathan Israel.[48][49] Enlightenment thought was deeply influential in the political realm. European rulers such as Catherine II of Russia, Joseph II of Austria, and Frederick II of Prussia tried to apply Enlightenment thought on religious and political tolerance, which became known as enlightened absolutism.[14] Many of the major political and intellectual figures behind the American Revolution associated themselves closely with the Enlightenment: Benjamin Franklin visited Europe repeatedly and contributed actively to the scientific and political debates there and brought the newest ideas back to Philadelphia; Thomas Jefferson closely followed European ideas and later incorporated some of the ideals of the Enlightenment into the Declaration of Independence; and Madison incorporated these ideals into the U.S. Constitution during its framing in 1787.[50]

Theories of government[edit]

Locke, one of the most influential Enlightenment thinkers,[51] based his governance philosophy in social contract theory, a subject that permeated Enlightenment political thought. English philosopher Thomas Hobbes ushered in this new debate with his work Leviathan in 1651. Hobbes also developed some of the fundamentals of European liberal thought: the right of the individual, the natural equality of all men, the artificial character of the political order (which led to the later distinction between civil society and the state), the view that all legitimate political power must be «representative» and based on the consent of the people, and a liberal interpretation of law which leaves people free to do whatever the law does not explicitly forbid.[52]

Both Locke and Rousseau developed social contract theories in Two Treatises of Government and Discourse on Inequality, respectively. While quite different works, Locke, Hobbes, and Rousseau agreed that a social contract, in which the government’s authority lies in the consent of the governed,[53] is necessary for man to live in civil society. Locke defines the state of nature as a condition in which humans are rational and follow natural law, in which all men are born equal and with the right to life, liberty, and property. However, when one citizen breaks the law of nature both the transgressor and the victim enter into a state of war, from which it is virtually impossible to break free. Therefore, Locke said that individuals enter into civil society to protect their natural rights via an «unbiased judge» or common authority, such as courts. In contrast, Rousseau’s conception relies on the supposition that «civil man» is corrupted, while «natural man» has no want he cannot fulfill himself. Natural man is only taken out of the state of nature when the inequality associated with private property is established.[54] Rousseau said that people join into civil society via the social contract to achieve unity while preserving individual freedom. This is embodied in the sovereignty of the general will, the moral and collective legislative body constituted by citizens.

Locke is known for his statement that individuals have a right to «Life, Liberty, and Property,» and his belief that the natural right to property is derived from labor. Tutored by Locke, Anthony Ashley-Cooper, 3rd Earl of Shaftesbury, wrote in 1706: «There is a mighty Light which spreads its self over the world especially in those two free Nations of England and Holland; on whom the Affairs of Europe now turn.»[55] Locke’s theory of natural rights has influenced many political documents, including the U.S. Declaration of Independence and the French National Constituent Assembly’s Declaration of the Rights of Man and of the Citizen.

The philosophes argued that the establishment of a contractual basis of rights would lead to the market mechanism and capitalism, the scientific method, religious tolerance, and the organization of states into self-governing republics through democratic means. In this view, the tendency of the philosophes in particular to apply rationality to every problem is considered the essential change.[56]

Although much of Enlightenment political thought was dominated by social contract theorists, Hume and Ferguson criticized this camp. Hume’s essay Of the Original Contract argues that governments derived from consent are rarely seen and civil government is grounded in a ruler’s habitual authority and force. It is precisely because of the ruler’s authority over-and-against the subject that the subject tacitly consents, and Hume says that the subjects would «never imagine that their consent made him sovereign», rather the authority did so.[57] Similarly, Ferguson did not believe citizens built the state, rather polities grew out of social development. In his 1767 An Essay on the History of Civil Society, Ferguson uses the four stages of progress, a theory that was popular in Scotland at the time, to explain how humans advance from a hunting and gathering society to a commercial and civil society without agreeing to a social contract.

Both Rousseau’s and Locke’s social contract theories rest on the presupposition of natural rights, which are not a result of law or custom but are things that all men have in pre-political societies and are therefore universal and inalienable. The most famous natural right formulation comes from Locke’s Second Treatise, when he introduces the state of nature. For Locke, the law of nature is grounded on mutual security or the idea that one cannot infringe on another’s natural rights, as every man is equal and has the same inalienable rights. These natural rights include perfect equality and freedom, as well as the right to preserve life and property.

Locke argues against indentured servitude on the basis that enslaving oneself goes against the law of nature because a person cannot surrender their own rights: freedom is absolute, and no one can take it away. Locke argues that one person cannot enslave another because it is morally reprehensible, although he introduces a caveat by saying that enslavement of a lawful captive in time of war would not go against one’s natural rights. As a spill-over of the Enlightenment, nonsecular beliefs expressed first by Quakers and then by Protestant evangelicals in Britain and the United States emerged. To these groups, slavery became «repugnant to our religion» and a «crime in the sight of God».[58] These ideas added to those expressed by Enlightenment thinkers, leading many in Britain to believe that slavery was «not only morally wrong and economically inefficient, but also politically unwise.» This ideals eventually led to the abolition of slavery in Britain and the United States.[59]

Enlightened absolutism[edit]

The Marquis of Pombal, as the head of the government of Portugal, implemented sweeping socio-economic reforms

The leaders of the Enlightenment were not especially democratic, as they more often look to absolute monarchs as the key to imposing reforms designed by the intellectuals. Voltaire despised democracy and said the absolute monarch must be enlightened and must act as dictated by reason and justice—in other words, be a «philosopher-king».[60]

Denmark’s minister Johann Struensee, a social reformer, was publicly executed in 1772 for usurping royal authority

In several nations, rulers welcomed leaders of the Enlightenment at court and asked them to help design laws and programs to reform the system, typically to build stronger states. These rulers are called «enlightened despots» by historians.[61] They included Frederick the Great of Prussia, Catherine the Great of Russia, Leopold II of Tuscany and Joseph II of Austria. Joseph was over-enthusiastic, announcing many reforms that had little support so that revolts broke out and his regime became a comedy of errors, and nearly all his programs were reversed.[62] Senior ministers Pombal in Portugal and Johann Friedrich Struensee in Denmark also governed according to Enlightenment ideals. In Poland, the model constitution of 1791 expressed Enlightenment ideals, but was in effect for only one year before the nation was partitioned among its neighbors. More enduring were the cultural achievements, which created a nationalist spirit in Poland.[63]

Frederick the Great, the king of Prussia from 1740 to 1786, saw himself as a leader of the Enlightenment and patronized philosophers and scientists at his court in Berlin. Voltaire, who had been imprisoned and maltreated by the French government, was eager to accept Frederick’s invitation to live at his palace. Frederick explained: «My principal occupation is to combat ignorance and prejudice… to enlighten minds, cultivate morality, and to make people as happy as it suits human nature, and as the means at my disposal permit.»[64]

American Revolution and French Revolution[edit]

The Enlightenment has been frequently linked to the American Revolution of 1776[65] and the French Revolution of 1789—both had some intellectual influence from Thomas Jefferson.[66][67] One view of the political changes that occurred during the Enlightenment is that the «consent of the governed» philosophy as delineated by Locke in Two Treatises of Government (1689) represented a paradigm shift from the old governance paradigm under feudalism known as the «divine right of kings». In this view, the revolutions were caused by the fact that this governance paradigm shift often could not be resolved peacefully and therefore violent revolution was the result. A governance philosophy where the king was never wrong would be in direct conflict with one whereby citizens by natural law had to consent to the acts and rulings of their government.

Alexis de Tocqueville proposed the French Revolution as the inevitable result of the radical opposition created in the 18th century between the monarchy and the men of letters of the Enlightenment. These men of letters constituted a sort of «substitute aristocracy that was both all-powerful and without real power.» This illusory power came from the rise of «public opinion», born when absolutist centralization removed the nobility and the bourgeoisie from the political sphere. The «literary politics» that resulted promoted a discourse of equality and was hence in fundamental opposition to the monarchical regime.[68] De Tocqueville «clearly designates… the cultural effects of transformation in the forms of the exercise of power.»[69]

Religion[edit]

It does not require great art or magnificently trained eloquence, to prove that Christians should tolerate each other. I, however, am going further: I say that we should regard all men as our brothers. What? The Turk my brother? The Chinaman my brother? The Jew? The Siam? Yes, without doubt; are we not all children of the same father and creatures of the same God?

Voltaire (1763)[70]

Enlightenment era religious commentary was a response to the preceding century of religious conflict in Europe, especially the Thirty Years’ War.[71] Theologians of the Enlightenment wanted to reform their faith to its generally non-confrontational roots and to limit the capacity for religious controversy to spill over into politics and warfare while still maintaining a true faith in God. For moderate Christians, this meant a return to simple Scripture. Locke abandoned the corpus of theological commentary in favor of an «unprejudiced examination» of the Word of God alone. He determined the essence of Christianity to be a belief in Christ the redeemer and recommended avoiding more detailed debate.[72] Anthony Collins, one of the English freethinkers, published his «Essay concerning the Use of Reason in Propositions the Evidence whereof depends on Human Testimony» (1707), in which he rejects the distinction between «above reason» and «contrary to reason», and demands that revelation should conform to man’s natural ideas of God. In the Jefferson Bible, Thomas Jefferson (who adhered to Epicurean philosophy) went further and dropped any passages dealing with miracles, visitations of angels, and the resurrection of Jesus after his death, as he tried to extract the practical Christian moral code of the New Testament.[73]

Enlightenment scholars sought to curtail the political power of organized religion and thereby prevent another age of intolerant religious war.[74] Spinoza determined to remove politics from contemporary and historical theology (e.g., disregarding Judaic law).[75] Moses Mendelssohn advised affording no political weight to any organized religion but instead recommended that each person follow what they found most convincing.[76] They believed a good religion based in instinctive morals and a belief in God should not theoretically need force to maintain order in its believers, and both Mendelssohn and Spinoza judged religion on its moral fruits, not the logic of its theology.[77]

Several novel ideas about religion developed with the Enlightenment, including deism and talk of atheism. According to Thomas Paine, deism is the simple belief in God the Creator with no reference to the Bible or any other miraculous source. Instead, the deist relies solely on personal reason to guide his creed,[78] which was eminently agreeable to many thinkers of the time.[79] Atheism was much discussed, but there were few proponents. Wilson and Reill note: «In fact, very few enlightened intellectuals, even when they were vocal critics of Christianity, were true atheists. Rather, they were critics of orthodox belief, wedded rather to skepticism, deism, vitalism, or perhaps pantheism.»[80] Some followed Pierre Bayle and argued that atheists could indeed be moral men.[81] Many others like Voltaire held that without belief in a God who punishes evil, the moral order of society was undermined; that is, since atheists gave themselves to no supreme authority and no law and had no fear of eternal consequences, they were far more likely to disrupt society.[82] Bayle observed that, in his day, «prudent persons will always maintain an appearance of [religion],» and he believed that even atheists could hold concepts of honor and go beyond their own self-interest to create and interact in society.[83] Locke said that if there were no God and no divine law, the result would be moral anarchy: every individual «could have no law but his own will, no end but himself. He would be a god to himself, and the satisfaction of his own will the sole measure and end of all his actions.»[84]

Separation of church and state[edit]

The «Radical Enlightenment»[85][86] promoted the concept of separating church and state,[87] an idea that is often credited to Locke.[88] According to his principle of the social contract, Locke said that the government lacked authority in the realm of individual conscience, as this was something rational people could not cede to the government for it or others to control. For Locke, this created a natural right in the liberty of conscience, which he said must therefore remain protected from any government authority.

These views on religious tolerance and the importance of individual conscience, along with the social contract, became particularly influential in the American colonies and the drafting of the United States Constitution.[89] In a letter to the Danbury Baptist Association in Connecticut, Thomas Jefferson calls for a «wall of separation between church and state» at the federal level. He previously had supported successful efforts to disestablish the Church of England in Virginia[90] and authored the Virginia Statute for Religious Freedom.[91] Jefferson’s political ideals were greatly influenced by the writings of Locke, Bacon, and Newton,[92] whom he considered the three greatest men that ever lived.[93]

National variations[edit]

The Enlightenment took hold in most European countries and influenced nations globally, often with a specific local emphasis. For example, in France it became associated with anti-government and anti-Church radicalism, while in Germany it reached deep into the middle classes, where it expressed a spiritualistic and nationalistic tone without threatening governments or established churches.[94] Government responses varied widely. In France, the government was hostile, and the philosophes fought against its censorship, sometimes being imprisoned or hounded into exile. The British government, for the most part, ignored the Enlightenment’s leaders in England and Scotland, although it did give Newton a knighthood and a very lucrative government office.[6]

A common theme among most countries which derived Enlightenment ideas from Europe was the intentional non-inclusion of Enlightenment philosophies pertaining to slavery. Originally during the French Revolution, a revolution deeply inspired by Enlightenment philosophy, «France’s revolutionary government had denounced slavery, but the property-holding ‘revolutionaries’ then remembered their bank accounts.»[95] Slavery frequently showed the limitations of the Enlightenment ideology as it pertained to European colonialism, since many colonies of Europe operated on a plantation economy fueled by slave labor. In 1791, the Haitian Revolution, a slave rebellion by emancipated slaves against French colonial rule in the colony of Saint-Domingue, broke out. European nations and the United States, despite the strong support for Enlightenment ideals, refused to «[give support] to Saint-Domingue’s anti-colonial struggle.»[95]

Great Britain[edit]

England[edit]

The very existence of an English Enlightenment has been hotly debated by scholars. The majority of textbooks on British history make little or no mention of an English Enlightenment. Some surveys of the entire Enlightenment include England and others ignore it, although they do include coverage of such major intellectuals as Joseph Addison, Edward Gibbon, John Locke, Isaac Newton, Alexander Pope, Joshua Reynolds, and Jonathan Swift.[96] Freethinking, a term describing those who stood in opposition to the institution of the Church, and the literal belief in the Bible, can be said to have begun in England no later than 1713, when Anthony Collins wrote his «Discourse of Free-thinking», which gained substantial popularity. This essay attacked the clergy of all churches and was a plea for deism.

Roy Porter argues that the reasons for this neglect were the assumptions that the movement was primarily French-inspired, that it was largely a-religious or anti-clerical, and that it stood in outspoken defiance to the established order.[97] Porter admits that after the 1720s England could claim thinkers to equal Diderot, Voltaire, or Rousseau. However, its leading intellectuals such as Gibbon,[98] Edmund Burke and Samuel Johnson were all quite conservative and supportive of the standing order. Porter says the reason was that Enlightenment had come early to England and had succeeded such that the culture had accepted political liberalism, philosophical empiricism, and religious toleration, positions which intellectuals on the continent had to fight against powerful odds. Furthermore, England rejected the collectivism of the continent and emphasized the improvement of individuals as the main goal of enlightenment.[99]

One leader of the Scottish Enlightenment was Adam Smith, the father of modern economic science

Scotland[edit]

In the Scottish Enlightenment, the principles of sociability, equality, and utility were disseminated in schools and universities, many of which used sophisticated teaching methods which blended philosophy with daily life.[100] Scotland’s major cities created an intellectual infrastructure of mutually supporting institutions such as schools, universities, reading societies, libraries, periodicals, museums, and masonic lodges.[101] The Scottish network was «predominantly liberal Calvinist, Newtonian, and ‘design’ oriented in character which played a major role in the further development of the transatlantic Enlightenment».[102] In France, Voltaire said «we look to Scotland for all our ideas of civilization».[103] The focus of the Scottish Enlightenment ranged from intellectual and economic matters to the specifically scientific as in the work of William Cullen, physician and chemist; James Anderson, agronomist; Joseph Black, physicist and chemist; and James Hutton, the first modern geologist.[22][104]

Anglo-American colonies[edit]

Several Americans, especially Benjamin Franklin and Thomas Jefferson, played a major role in bringing Enlightenment ideas to the New World and in influencing British and French thinkers.[105] Franklin was influential for his political activism and for his advances in physics.[106][107] The cultural exchange during the Age of Enlightenment ran in both directions across the Atlantic. Thinkers such as Paine, Locke, and Rousseau all take Native American cultural practices as examples of natural freedom.[108] The Americans closely followed English and Scottish political ideas, as well as some French thinkers such as Montesquieu.[109] As deists, they were influenced by ideas of John Toland and Matthew Tindal. There was a great emphasis upon liberty, republicanism, and religious tolerance. There was no respect for monarchy or inherited political power. Deists reconciled science and religion by rejecting prophecies, miracles, and biblical theology. Leading deists included Thomas Paine in The Age of Reason and Thomas Jefferson in his short Jefferson Bible, from which he removed all supernatural aspects.[110]

German states[edit]

Prussia took the lead among the German states in sponsoring the political reforms that Enlightenment thinkers urged absolute rulers to adopt. There were important movements as well in the smaller states of Bavaria, Saxony, Hanover, and the Palatinate. In each case, Enlightenment values became accepted and led to significant political and administrative reforms that laid the groundwork for the creation of modern states.[111] The princes of Saxony, for example, carried out an impressive series of fundamental fiscal, administrative, judicial, educational, cultural, and general economic reforms. The reforms were aided by the country’s strong urban structure and influential commercial groups and modernized pre-1789 Saxony along the lines of classic Enlightenment principles.[112][113]

Before 1750, the German upper classes looked to France for intellectual, cultural, and architectural leadership, as French was the language of high society. By the mid-18th century, the Aufklärung (The Enlightenment) had transformed German high culture in music, philosophy, science, and literature. Christian Wolff was the pioneer as a writer who expounded the Enlightenment to German readers and legitimized German as a philosophic language.[114]

Johann Gottfried von Herder broke new ground in philosophy and poetry, as a leader of the Sturm und Drang movement of proto-Romanticism. Weimar Classicism (Weimarer Klassik) was a cultural and literary movement based in Weimar that sought to establish a new humanism by synthesizing Romantic, classical, and Enlightenment ideas. The movement (from 1772 until 1805) involved Herder as well as polymath Johann Wolfgang von Goethe and Friedrich Schiller, a poet and historian. Herder argued that every group of people had its own particular identity, which was expressed in its language and culture. This legitimized the promotion of German language and culture and helped shape the development of German nationalism. Schiller’s plays expressed the restless spirit of his generation, depicting the hero’s struggle against social pressures and the force of destiny.[115]

German music, sponsored by the upper classes, came of age under composers Johann Sebastian Bach, Joseph Haydn, and Wolfgang Amadeus Mozart.[116]

In remote Königsberg, Kant tried to reconcile rationalism and religious belief, individual freedom, and political authority. Kant’s work contained basic tensions that would continue to shape German thought—and indeed all of European philosophy—well into the 20th century.[117] German Enlightenment won the support of princes, aristocrats, and the middle classes, and it permanently reshaped the culture.[118] However, there was a conservatism among the elites that warned against going too far.[119]

In the 1780s, Lutheran ministers Johann Heinrich Schulz and Karl Wilhelm Brumbey got in trouble with their preaching as they were attacked and ridiculed by Kant, Wilhelm Abraham Teller and others. In 1788, Prussia issued an «Edict on Religion» that forbade preaching any sermon that undermined popular belief in the Holy Trinity and the Bible. The goal was to avoid skepticism, deism, and theological disputes that might impinge on domestic tranquility. Men who doubted the value of Enlightenment favoured the measure, but so too did many supporters. German universities had created a closed elite that could debate controversial issues among themselves, but spreading them to the public was seen as too risky. This intellectual elite was favoured by the state, but that might be reversed if the process of the Enlightenment proved politically or socially destabilizing.[120]

Habsburg monarchy[edit]

The reign of Maria Theresa, the first Habsburg monarch to be considered influenced by the Enlightenment in some areas, was marked by a mix of enlightenment and conservatism. Her son Joseph II’s brief reign was marked by this conflict, with his ideology of Josephinism facing opposition. Emperor Leopold II, who was an early opponent of capital punishment, had a brief and contentious rule that was mostly marked by relations with France. Similarly, Emperor Francis II’s rule was primarily marked by relations with France.

Italy[edit]

Statue of Cesare Beccaria, widely considered one of the greatest thinkers of the Age of Enlightenment.

In Italy the main centers of diffusion of the Enlightenment were Naples and Milan:[121] in both cities the intellectuals took public office and collaborated with the Bourbon and Habsburg administrations. In Naples, Antonio Genovesi, Ferdinando Galiani, and Gaetano Filangieri were active under the tolerant King Charles of Bourbon. However, the Neapolitan Enlightenment, like Vico’s philosophy, remained almost always in the theoretical field.[122] Only later, many Enlighteners animated the unfortunate experience of the Parthenopean Republic. In Milan, however, the movement strove to find concrete solutions to problems. The center of discussions was the magazine Il Caffè (1762–1766), founded by brothers Pietro and Alessandro Verri (famous philosophers and writers, as well as their brother Giovanni), who also gave life to the Accademia dei Pugni, founded in 1761. Minor centers were Tuscany, Veneto, and Piedmont, where among others, Pompeo Neri worked.

From Naples, Genovesi influenced a generation of southern Italian intellectuals and university students. His textbook Della diceosina, o sia della Filosofia del Giusto e dell’Onesto (1766) was a controversial attempt to mediate between the history of moral philosophy on the one hand and the specific problems encountered by 18th-century commercial society on the other. It contained the greater part of Genovesi’s political, philosophical, and economic thought, which became a guidebook for Neapolitan economic and social development.[123]

Science flourished as Alessandro Volta and Luigi Galvani made break-through discoveries in electricity. Pietro Verri was a leading economist in Lombardy. Historian Joseph Schumpeter states he was «the most important pre-Smithian authority on Cheapness-and-Plenty».[124] The most influential scholar on the Italian Enlightenment has been Franco Venturi.[125][126] Italy also produced some of the Enlightenment’s greatest legal theorists, including Beccaria, Giambattista Vico, and Francesco Mario Pagano.

Spain and Spanish America[edit]

When Charles II, the last Spanish Habsburg monarch, died in 1700, it touched out a major European conflict about succession and the fate of Spain and the Spanish Empire. The War of the Spanish Succession (1700–1715) brought Bourbon Prince Philip, Duke of Anjou to the throne of Spain as Philip V. Under the 1715 Treaty of Utrecht, the French and the Spanish Bourbons could not unite, with Philip renouncing any rights to the French throne. The political restriction did not impede strong French influence of the Age of Enlightenment on Spain, the Spanish monarchs, the Spanish Empire.[127][128] Philip came into effective power in 1715 and began implementing administrative reforms to try to stop the decline of the Spanish Empire.

Under Charles III, the crown began to implement serious structural changes, generally known as the Bourbon Reforms. The crown curtailed the power of the Catholic Church and the clergy, established a standing military in Spanish America, established new viceroyalties and reorganized administrative districts into intendants. Freer trade was promoted under comercio libre in which regions could trade with companies sailing from any other Spanish port, rather than the restrictive mercantile system. The crown sent out scientific expeditions to assert Spanish sovereignty over territories it claimed but did not control, but also importantly to discover the economic potential of its far-flung empire. Botanical expeditions sought plants that could be of use to the empire.[129]

One of the best acts by Charles IV, a monarch not notable for his good judgment, was to give Prussian scientist Alexander von Humboldt free rein to travel and gather information about the Spanish Empire during his five-year, self-funded expedition. Crown officials were to aid Humboldt in any way they could, so that he was able to get access to expert information. Given that Spain’s empire was closed to foreigners, Humboldt’s unfettered access is quite remarkable. His observations of New Spain, published as the Political Essay on the Kingdom of New Spain remains an important scientific and historical text.[130]

When Napoleon invaded Spain in 1808, Ferdinand VII abdicated and Napoleon placed his brother Joseph Bonaparte on the throne. To add legitimacy to this move, the Bayonne Constitution was promulgated, which included representation from Spain’s overseas components, but most Spaniards rejected the whole Napoleonic project. A war of national resistance erupted. The Cortes de Cádiz (parliament) was convened to rule Spain in the absence of the legitimate monarch, Ferdinand. It created a new governing document, the Constitution of 1812, which laid out three branches of government: executive, legislative, and judicial; put limits on the king by creating a constitutional monarchy; defined citizens as those in the Spanish Empire without African ancestry; established universal manhood suffrage; and established public education starting with primary school through university as well as freedom of expression. The constitution was in effect from 1812 until 1814, when Napoleon was defeated and Ferdinand was restored to the throne of Spain. Upon his return, Ferdinand repudiated the constitution and reestablished absolutist rule.[131]

The French invasion of Spain sparked a crisis of legitimacy of rule in Spanish America, with many regions establishing juntas to rule in the name of Ferdinand VII. Most of Spanish America fought for independence, leaving only Cuba and Puerto Rico as well as the Philippines as overseas components of the Spanish Empire until the Spanish–American War in 1898. All newly independent and sovereign nations became republics by 1824, with written constitutions. Mexico’s brief post-independence monarchy was overthrown and replaced by a federal republic under the Constitution of 1824, inspired by both the U.S. and Spanish constitutions.

Haiti[edit]

The Haitian Revolution began in 1791 and ended in 1804 and shows how Enlightenment ideas «were part of complex transcultural flows.»[3] Radical ideas in Paris during and after the French Revolution were mobilized in Haiti, such as by Toussaint L’Ouverture.[3] Toussaint had read the critique of European colonialism in Guillaume Thomas Raynal’s book Histoire des deux Indes and «was particularly impressed by Raynal’s prediction of the coming of a ‘Black Spartacus.«[3]

The revolution combined Enlightenment ideas with the experiences of the slaves in Haiti, two-thirds of whom had been born in Africa and could «draw on specific notions of kingdom and just government from Western and Central Africa, and to employ religious practices such as voodoo for the formation of revolutionary communities.»[3] The revolution also affected France and «forced the French National Convention to abolish slavery in 1794.»[3]

Portugal[edit]

The Enlightenment in Portugal (Iluminismo) was heavily marked by the rule of Prime Minister Marquis of Pombal under King Joseph I from 1756 to 1777. Following the 1755 Lisbon earthquake which destroyed a large part of Lisbon, the Marquis of Pombal implemented important economic policies to regulate commercial activity (in particular with Brazil and England), and to standardise quality throughout the country (for example by introducing the first integrated industries in Portugal). His reconstruction of Lisbon’s riverside district in straight and perpendicular streets (the Lisbon Baixa), methodically organized to facilitate commerce and exchange (for example by assigning to each street a different product or service), can be seen as a direct application of the Enlightenment ideas to governance and urbanism. His urbanistic ideas, also being the first large-scale example of earthquake engineering, became collectively known as Pombaline style, and were implemented throughout the kingdom during his stay in office. His governance was as enlightened as ruthless, see for example the Távora affair.

In literature, the first Enlightenment ideas in Portugal can be traced back to the diplomat, philosopher, and writer António Vieira[132] who spent a considerable amount of his life in colonial Brazil denouncing discriminations against New Christians and the indigenous peoples in Brazil. During the 18th century, enlightened literary movements such as the Arcádia Lusitana (lasting from 1756 until 1776, then replaced by the Nova Arcádia in 1790 until 1794) surfaced in the academic medium, in particular involving former students of the University of Coimbra. A distinct member of this group was the poet Manuel Maria Barbosa du Bocage. The physician António Nunes Ribeiro Sanches was also an important Enlightenment figure, contributing to the Encyclopédie and being part of the Russian court. The ideas of the Enlightenment influenced various economists and anti-colonial intellectuals throughout the Portuguese Empire, such as José de Azeredo Coutinho, José da Silva Lisboa, Cláudio Manoel da Costa, and Tomás Antônio Gonzaga.

The Napoleonic invasion of Portugal had consequences for the Portuguese monarchy. With the aid of the British navy, the Portuguese royal family was evacuated to Brazil, its most important colony. Even though Napoleon had been defeated, the royal court remained in Brazil. The Liberal Revolution of 1820 forced the return of the royal family to Portugal. The terms by which the restored king was to rule was a constitutional monarchy under the Constitution of Portugal. Brazil declared its independence of Portugal in 1822 and became a monarchy.

Russia[edit]

In Russia, the government began to actively encourage the proliferation of arts and sciences in the mid-18th century. This era produced the first Russian university, library, theatre, public museum, and independent press. Like other enlightened despots, Catherine the Great played a key role in fostering the arts, sciences and education. She used her own interpretation of Enlightenment ideals, assisted by notable international experts such as Voltaire (by correspondence) and in residence world class scientists such as Leonhard Euler and Peter Simon Pallas. The national Enlightenment differed from its Western European counterpart in that it promoted further modernization of all aspects of Russian life and was concerned with attacking the institution of serfdom in Russia. The Russian Enlightenment centered on the individual instead of societal enlightenment and encouraged the living of an enlightened life.[133][134] A powerful element was prosveshchenie which combined religious piety, erudition, and commitment to the spread of learning. However, it lacked the skeptical and critical spirit of the Western European Enlightenment.[135]

Poland and Lithuania[edit]

Enlightenment ideas (oświecenie) emerged late in Poland, as the Polish middle class was weaker and szlachta (nobility) culture (Sarmatism) together with the Polish–Lithuanian Commonwealth political system (Golden Liberty) were in deep crisis. The political system was built on aristocratic republicanism, but was unable to defend itself against powerful neighbors Russia, Prussia, and Austria as they repeatedly sliced off regions until nothing was left of independent Poland. The period of Polish Enlightenment began in the 1730s–1740s and especially in theatre and the arts peaked in the reign of King Stanisław August Poniatowski (second half of the 18th century).

Warsaw was a main centre after 1750, with an expansion of schools and educational institutions and the arts patronage held at the Royal Castle.[136] Leaders promoted tolerance and more education. They included King Stanislaw II August and reformers Piotr Switkowski, Antoni Poplawski, Josef Niemcewicz, and Jósef Pawlinkowski, as well as Baudouin de Cortenay, a Polonized dramatist. Opponents included Florian Jaroszewicz, Gracjan Piotrowski, Karol Wyrwicz, and Wojciech Skarszewski.[137] The movement went into decline with the Third Partition of Poland (1795) – a national tragedy inspiring a short period of sentimental writing – and ended in 1822, replaced by Romanticism.[138]

China[edit]

Eighteenth-century China experienced «a trend towards seeing fewer dragons and miracles, not unlike the disenchantment that began to spread across the Europe of the Enlightenment.»[3] Furthermore, «some of the developments that we associate with Europe’s Enlightenment resemble events in China remarkably.»[3] During this time, ideals of Chinese society were reflected in «the reign of the Qing emperors Kangxi and Qianlong; China was posited as the incarnation of an enlightened and meritocratic society—and instrumentalized for criticisms of absolutist rule in Europe.»[3]

Japan[edit]

From 1641 to 1853, the Tokugawa shogunate of Japan enforced a policy called kaikin. The policy prohibited foreign contact with most outside countries.[139] Robert Bellah found «origins of modern Japan in certain strands of Confucian thinking, a ‘functional analogue to the Protestant Ethic’ that Max Weber singled out as the driving force behind Western capitalism.»[3] Japanese Confucian and Enlightenment ideas were brought together, for example, in the work of the Japanese reformer Tsuda Mamichi in the 1870s, who said, «Whenever we open our mouths…it is to speak of ‘enlightenment.«[3]

In Japan and much of East Asia, Confucian ideas were not replaced but «ideas associated with the Enlightenment were instead fused with the existing cosmology—which in turn was refashioned under conditions of global interaction.»[3] In Japan in particular, the term ri, which is the Confucian idea of «order and harmony on human society» also came to represent «the idea of laissez-faire and the rationality of market exchange.»[3] By the 1880s, the slogan «Civilization and Enlightenment» became potent throughout Japan, China, and Korea and was employed to address challenges of globalization.[3]

Korea[edit]

During this time, Korea «aimed at isolation» and was known as the «hermit kingdom» but became awakened to Enlightenment ideas by the 1890s such as with the activities of the Independence Club.[3] Korea was influenced by China and Japan but also found its own Enlightenment path with the Korean intellectual Yu Kilchun who popularized the term Enlightenment throughout Korea.[3] The use of Enlightenment ideas was a «response to a specific situation in Korea in the 1890s, and not a belated answer to Voltaire.»[3]

India[edit]

In 18th century India, Tipu Sultan was an enlightened monarch, who «was one of the founding members of the (French) Jacobin Club in Seringapatam, had planted a liberty tree, and asked to be addressed as ‘Tipu Citoyen,» which means Citizen Tipu.[3] In parts of India, an important movement called the «Bengal Renaissance» led to Enlightenment reforms beginning in the 1820s.[3] Ram Mohan Roy was a reformer who «fused different traditions in his project of social reform that made him a proponent of a ‘religion of reason.«[3]

Egypt[edit]

Eighteenth-century Egypt had «a form of ‘cultural revival’ in the making—specifically Islamic origins of modernization long before Napoleon’s Egyptian campaign.»[3] Napoleon’s expedition into Egypt further encouraged «social transformations that harkened back to debates about inner-Islamic reform, but now were also legitimized by referring to the authority of the Enlightenment.»[3] A major intellectual influence on Islamic modernism and expanding the Enlightenment in Egypt, Rifa al-Tahtawi «oversaw the publication of hundreds of European works in the Arabic language.»[3]

Ottoman Empire[edit]

The Enlightenment began to influence the Ottoman Empire in the 1830s and continued into the late 19th century.[3]
The Tanzimat was a period of reform in the Ottoman Empire that began with the Gülhane Hatt-ı Şerif in 1839 and ended with the First Constitutional Era in 1876.

Namik Kemal, a political activist and member of the Young Ottomans, drew on major Enlightenment thinkers and «a variety of intellectual resources in his quest for social and political reform.»[3] In 1893, Kemal responded to Ernest Renan, who had indicted the Islamic religion, with his own version of the Enlightenment, which «was not a poor copy of French debates in the eighteenth century, but an original position responding to the exigencies of Ottoman society in the late nineteenth century.»[3]

Historiography[edit]

The Enlightenment has always been contested territory. According to Keith Thomas, its supporters «hail it as the source of everything that is progressive about the modern world. For them, it stands for freedom of thought, rational inquiry, critical thinking, religious tolerance, political liberty, scientific achievement, the pursuit of happiness, and hope for the future.»[140] Thomas adds that its detractors accuse it of shallow rationalism, naïve optimism, unrealistic universalism, and moral darkness. From the start, conservative and clerical defenders of traditional religion attacked materialism and skepticism as evil forces that encouraged immorality. By 1794, they pointed to the Reign of Terror during the French Revolution as confirmation of their predictions.

As the Enlightenment was ending, Romantic philosophers argued that excessive dependence on reason was a mistake perpetuated by the Enlightenment because it disregarded the bonds of history, myth, faith, and tradition that were necessary to hold society together.[141] Ritchie Robertson portrays it as a grand intellectual and political program, offering a «science» of society modeled on the powerful physical laws of Newton. «Social science» was seen as the instrument of human improvement. It would expose truth and expand human happiness.[142]

Definition[edit]

The term «Enlightenment» emerged in English in the latter part of the 19th century,[143] with particular reference to French philosophy, as the equivalent of the French term Lumières (used first by Jean-Baptiste Dubos in 1733 and already well established by 1751). From Kant’s 1784 essay «Beantwortung der Frage: Was ist Aufklärung?» («Answering the Question: What is Enlightenment?»), the German term became Aufklärung (aufklären=to illuminate; sich aufklären=to clear up). However, scholars have never agreed on a definition of the Enlightenment or on its chronological or geographical extent. Terms like les Lumières (French), illuminismo (Italian), ilustración (Spanish) and Aufklärung (German) referred to partly overlapping movements. Not until the late 19th century did English scholars agree they were talking about «the Enlightenment».[141][144]

If there is something you know, communicate it. If there is something you don’t know, search for it.

— An engraving from the 1772 edition of the Encyclopédie; Truth, in the top center, is surrounded by light and unveiled by the figures to the right, Philosophy and Reason

Enlightenment historiography began in the period itself, from what Enlightenment figures said about their work. A dominant element was the intellectual angle they took. Jean le Rond d’Alembert’s Preliminary Discourse of l’Encyclopédie provides a history of the Enlightenment which comprises a chronological list of developments in the realm of knowledge—of which the Encyclopédie forms the pinnacle.[145] In 1783, Mendelssohn referred to Enlightenment as a process by which man was educated in the use of reason.[146] Kant called Enlightenment «man’s release from his self-incurred tutelage», tutelage being «man’s inability to make use of his understanding without direction from another».[147] «For Kant, Enlightenment was mankind’s final coming of age, the emancipation of the human consciousness from an immature state of ignorance».[148] The German scholar Ernst Cassirer called the Enlightenment «a part and a special phase of that whole intellectual development through which modern philosophic thought gained its characteristic self-confidence and self-consciousness».[149] According to historian Roy Porter, the liberation of the human mind from a dogmatic state of ignorance, is the epitome of what the Age of Enlightenment was trying to capture.[150]

Bertrand Russell saw the Enlightenment as a phase in a progressive development which began in antiquity and that reason and challenges to the established order were constant ideals throughout that time.[151] Russell said that the Enlightenment was ultimately born out of the Protestant reaction against the Catholic Counter-Reformation and that philosophical views such as affinity for democracy against monarchy originated among 16th-century Protestants to justify their desire to break away from the Catholic Church. Although many of these philosophical ideals were picked up by Catholics, Russell argues that by the 18th century the Enlightenment was the principal manifestation of the schism that began with Martin Luther.[151]

Jonathan Israel rejects the attempts of postmodern and Marxian historians to understand the revolutionary ideas of the period purely as by-products of social and economic transformations.[152] He instead focuses on the history of ideas in the period from 1650 to the end of the 18th century and claims that it was the ideas themselves that caused the change that eventually led to the revolutions of the latter half of the 18th century and the early 19th century.[153] Israel argues that until the 1650s Western civilization «was based on a largely shared core of faith, tradition, and authority».[154]

Time span[edit]

There is little consensus on the precise beginning of the Age of Enlightenment, though several historians and philosophers argue that it was marked by Descartes’ 1637 philosophy of Cogito, ergo sum («I think, therefore I am»), which shifted the epistemological basis from external authority to internal certainty.[155][156][157] In France, many cited the publication of Newton’s Principia Mathematica (1687),[158] which built upon the work of earlier scientists and formulated the laws of motion and universal gravitation.[159] The middle of the 17th century (1650) or the beginning of the 18th century (1701) are often used as epochs.[citation needed] French historians usually place the Siècle des Lumières («Century of Enlightenments») between 1715 and 1789: from the beginning of the reign of Louis XV until the French Revolution.[160] Most scholars use the last years of the century, often choosing the French Revolution or the beginning of the Napoleonic Wars (1804) as a convenient point in time with which to date the end of the Enlightenment.[161]

In recent years, scholars have expanded the time span and global perspective of the Enlightenment by examining: (1) how European intellectuals did not work alone and other people helped spread and adapt Enlightenment ideas, (2) how Enlightenment ideas were «a response to cross-border interaction and global integration», and (3) how the Enlightenment «continued throughout the nineteenth century and beyond.»[3] The Enlightenment «was not merely a history of diffusion» and «was the work of historical actors around the world… who invoked the term… for their own specific purposes.»[3]

Modern study[edit]

In the 1947 book Dialectic of Enlightenment, Frankfurt School philosophers Max Horkheimer and Theodor W. Adorno argue:

Enlightenment, understood in the widest sense as the advance of thought, has always aimed at liberating human beings from fear and installing them as masters. Yet the wholly enlightened earth radiates under the sign of disaster triumphant.[162]

Extending Horkheimer and Adorno’s argument, intellectual historian Jason Josephson Storm argues that any idea of the Age of Enlightenment as a clearly defined period that is separate from the earlier Renaissance and later Romanticism or Counter-Enlightenment constitutes a myth. Storm points out that there are vastly different and mutually contradictory periodizations of the Enlightenment depending on nation, field of study, and school of thought; that the term and category of «Enlightenment» referring to the Scientific Revolution was actually applied after the fact; that the Enlightenment did not see an increase in disenchantment or the dominance of the mechanistic worldview; and that a blur in the early modern ideas of the humanities and natural sciences makes it hard to circumscribe a Scientific Revolution.[163] Storm defends his categorization of the Enlightenment as «myth» by noting the regulative role ideas of a period of Enlightenment and disenchantment play in modern Western culture, such that belief in magic, spiritualism, and even religion appears somewhat taboo in intellectual strata.[164]

In the 1970s, study of the Enlightenment expanded to include the ways Enlightenment ideas spread to European colonies and how they interacted with indigenous cultures and how the Enlightenment took place in formerly unstudied areas such as Italy, Greece, the Balkans, Poland, Hungary, and Russia.[165] Intellectuals such as Robert Darnton and Jürgen Habermas have focused on the social conditions of the Enlightenment. Habermas described the creation of the «bourgeois public sphere» in 18th-century Europe, containing the new venues and modes of communication allowing for rational exchange. Habermas said that the public sphere was bourgeois, egalitarian, rational, and independent from the state, making it the ideal venue for intellectuals to critically examine contemporary politics and society, away from the interference of established authority. While the public sphere is generally an integral component of the social study of the Enlightenment, other historians[note 3] have questioned whether the public sphere had these characteristics.

Society and culture[edit]

In contrast to the intellectual historiographical approach of the Enlightenment, which examines the various currents or discourses of intellectual thought within the European context during the 17th and 18th centuries, the cultural (or social) approach examines the changes that occurred in European society and culture. This approach studies the process of changing sociabilities and cultural practices during the Enlightenment.

One of the primary elements of the culture of the Enlightenment was the rise of the public sphere, a «realm of communication marked by new arenas of debate, more open and accessible forms of urban public space and sociability, and an explosion of print culture», in the late 17th century and 18th century.[166] Elements of the public sphere included that it was egalitarian, that it discussed the domain of «common concern», and that argument was founded on reason.[167] Habermas uses the term «common concern» to describe those areas of political/social knowledge and discussion that were previously the exclusive territory of the state and religious authorities, now open to critical examination by the public sphere. The values of this bourgeois public sphere included holding reason to be supreme, considering everything to be open to criticism (the public sphere is critical), and the opposition of secrecy of all sorts.[168]

German explorer Alexander von Humboldt showed his disgust for slavery and often criticized the colonial policies—he always acted out of a deeply humanistic conviction, borne by the ideas of the Enlightenment.[169]

The creation of the public sphere has been associated with two long-term historical trends: the rise of the modern nation state and the rise of capitalism. The modern nation state in its consolidation of public power created by counterpoint a private realm of society independent of the state, which allowed for the public sphere. Capitalism also increased society’s autonomy and self-awareness, as well as an increasing need for the exchange of information. As the nascent public sphere expanded, it embraced a large variety of institutions, and the most commonly cited were coffee houses and cafés, salons and the literary public sphere, figuratively localized in the Republic of Letters.[170] In France, the creation of the public sphere was helped by the aristocracy’s move from the king’s palace at Versailles to Paris in about 1720, since their rich spending stimulated the trade in luxuries and artistic creations, especially fine paintings.[171]

The context for the rise of the public sphere was the economic and social change commonly associated with the Industrial Revolution: «Economic expansion, increasing urbanization, rising population and improving communications in comparison to the stagnation of the previous century».[172] Rising efficiency in production techniques and communication lowered the prices of consumer goods and increased the amount and variety of goods available to consumers (including the literature essential to the public sphere). Meanwhile, the colonial experience (most European states had colonial empires in the 18th century) began to expose European society to extremely heterogeneous cultures, leading to the breaking down of «barriers between cultural systems, religious divides, gender differences and geographical areas».[173]

The word «public» implies the highest level of inclusivity—the public sphere by definition should be open to all. However, this sphere was only public to relative degrees. Enlightenment thinkers frequently contrasted their conception of the «public» with that of the people: Condorcet contrasted «opinion» with populace, Marmontel «the opinion of men of letters» with «the opinion of the multitude» and d’Alembert the «truly enlightened public» with «the blind and noisy multitude».[174] Additionally, most institutions of the public sphere excluded both women and the lower classes.[175] Cross-class influences occurred through noble and lower class participation in areas such as the coffeehouses and the Masonic lodges.

Implications in the arts[edit]

Because of the focus on reason over superstition, the Enlightenment cultivated the arts.[176] Emphasis on learning, art, and music became more widespread, especially with the growing middle class. Areas of study such as literature, philosophy, science, and the fine arts increasingly explored subject matter to which the general public, in addition to the previously more segregated professionals and patrons, could relate.[177]

As musicians depended more on public support, public concerts became increasingly popular and helped supplement performers’ and composers’ incomes. The concerts also helped them to reach a wider audience. Handel, for example, epitomized this with his highly public musical activities in London. He gained considerable fame there with performances of his operas and oratorios. The music of Haydn and Mozart, with their Viennese Classical styles, are usually regarded as being the most in line with the Enlightenment ideals.[178]

The desire to explore, record, and systematize knowledge had a meaningful impact on music publications. Rousseau’s Dictionnaire de musique (published 1767 in Geneva and 1768 in Paris) was a leading text in the late 18th century.[178] This widely available dictionary gave short definitions of words like genius and taste and was clearly influenced by the Enlightenment movement. Another text influenced by Enlightenment values was Charles Burney’s A General History of Music: From the Earliest Ages to the Present Period (1776), which was a historical survey and an attempt to rationalize elements in music systematically over time.[179] Recently, musicologists have shown renewed interest in the ideas and consequences of the Enlightenment. For example, Rose Rosengard Subotnik’s Deconstructive Variations (subtitled Music and Reason in Western Society) compares Mozart’s Die Zauberflöte (1791) using the Enlightenment and Romantic perspectives and concludes that the work is «an ideal musical representation of the Enlightenment».[179]

As the economy and the middle class expanded, there was an increasing number of amateur musicians. One manifestation of this involved women, who became more involved with music on a social level. Women were already engaged in professional roles as singers and increased their presence in the amateur performers’ scene, especially with keyboard music.[180] Music publishers begin to print music that amateurs could understand and play. The majority of the works that were published were for keyboard, voice and keyboard, and chamber ensemble.[180] After these initial genres were popularized, from the mid-century on, amateur groups sang choral music, which then became a new trend for publishers to capitalize on. The increasing study of the fine arts, as well as access to amateur-friendly published works, led to more people becoming interested in reading and discussing music. Music magazines, reviews, and critical works which suited amateurs as well as connoisseurs began to surface.[180]

Dissemination of ideas[edit]

The philosophes spent a great deal of energy disseminating their ideas among educated men and women in cosmopolitan cities. They used many venues, some of them quite new.

Republic of Letters[edit]

The term «Republic of Letters» was coined in 1664 by Pierre Bayle in his journal Nouvelles de la Republique des Lettres. Towards the end of the 18th century, the editor of Histoire de la République des Lettres en France, a literary survey, described the Republic of Letters as being:

In the midst of all the governments that decide the fate of men; in the bosom of so many states, the majority of them despotic … there exists a certain realm which holds sway only over the mind … that we honor with the name Republic, because it preserves a measure of independence, and because it is almost its essence to be free. It is the realm of talent and of thought.[181]

The Republic of Letters was the sum of a number of Enlightenment ideals: an egalitarian realm governed by knowledge that could act across political boundaries and rival state power.[181] It was a forum that supported «free public examination of questions regarding religion or legislation».[182] Kant considered written communication essential to his conception of the public sphere; once everyone was a part of the «reading public», then society could be said to be enlightened.[183] The people who participated in the Republic of Letters, such as Diderot and Voltaire, are frequently known today as important Enlightenment figures. Indeed, the men who wrote Diderot’s Encyclopédie arguably formed a microcosm of the larger «republic».[184]

Many women played an essential part in the French Enlightenment because of the role they played as salonnières in Parisian salons, as the contrast to the male philosophes. The salon was the principal social institution of the republic[185] and «became the civil working spaces of the project of Enlightenment». Women, as salonnières, were «the legitimate governors of [the] potentially unruly discourse» that took place within.[186] While women were marginalized in the public culture of the Old Regime, the French Revolution destroyed the old cultural and economic restraints of patronage and corporatism (guilds), opening French society to female participation, particularly in the literary sphere.[187]

In France, the established men of letters (gens de lettres) had fused with the elites (les grands) of French society by the mid-18th century. This led to the creation of an oppositional literary sphere, Grub Street, the domain of a «multitude of versifiers and would-be authors».[188] These men came to London to become authors only to discover that the literary market could not support large numbers of writers, who in any case were very poorly remunerated by the publishing-bookselling guilds.[189]

The writers of Grub Street, the Grub Street Hacks, were left feeling bitter about the relative success of the men of letters[190] and found an outlet for their literature which was typified by the libelle. Written mostly in the form of pamphlets, the libelles «slandered the court, the Church, the aristocracy, the academies, the salons, everything elevated and respectable, including the monarchy itself».[191] Le Gazetier cuirassé by Charles Théveneau de Morande was a prototype of the genre. It was Grub Street literature that was most read by the public during the Enlightenment.[192] According to Darnton, more importantly the Grub Street hacks inherited the «revolutionary spirit» once displayed by the philosophes and paved the way for the French Revolution by desacralizing figures of political, moral, and religious authority in France.[193]

Book industry[edit]

ESTC data 1477–1799 by decade given with a regional differentiation

The increased consumption of reading materials of all sorts was one of the key features of the «social» Enlightenment. Developments in the Industrial Revolution allowed consumer goods to be produced in greater quantities at lower prices, encouraging the spread of books, pamphlets, newspapers, and journals – «media of the transmission of ideas and attitudes». Commercial development likewise increased the demand for information, along with rising populations and increased urbanisation.[194] However, demand for reading material extended outside of the realm of the commercial and outside the realm of the upper and middle classes, as evidenced by the bibliothèque bleue. Literacy rates are difficult to gauge, but in France the rates doubled over the course of the 18th century.[195] Reflecting the decreasing influence of religion, the number of books about science and art published in Paris doubled from 1720 to 1780, while the number of books about religion dropped to just one-tenth of the total.[21]

Reading underwent serious changes in the 18th century. In particular, Rolf Engelsing has argued for the existence of a reading revolution. Until 1750, reading was done intensively: people tended to own a small number of books and read them repeatedly, often to small audience. After 1750, people began to read «extensively», finding as many books as they could, increasingly reading them alone.[196] This is supported by increasing literacy rates, particularly among women.[197]

The vast majority of the reading public could not afford to own a private library, and while most of the state-run «universal libraries» set up in the 17th and 18th centuries were open to the public, they were not the only sources of reading material. On one end of the spectrum was the bibliothèque bleue, a collection of cheaply produced books published in Troyes, France. Intended for a largely rural and semi-literate audience these books included almanacs, retellings of medieval romances and condensed versions of popular novels, among other things. While some historians have argued against the Enlightenment’s penetration into the lower classes, the bibliothèque bleue represents at least a desire to participate in Enlightenment sociability.[198] Moving up the classes, a variety of institutions offered readers access to material without needing to buy anything. Libraries that lent out their material for a small price started to appear, and occasionally bookstores would offer a small lending library to their patrons. Coffee houses commonly offered books, journals, and sometimes even popular novels to their customers. Tatler and The Spectator, two influential periodicals sold from 1709 to 1714, were closely associated with coffee house culture in London, being both read and produced in various establishments in the city.[199] This is an example of the triple or even quadruple function of the coffee house: reading material was often obtained, read, discussed, and even produced on the premises.[200]

It is difficult to determine what people actually read during the Enlightenment. For example, examining the catalogs of private libraries gives an image skewed in favor of the classes wealthy enough to afford libraries and also ignores censored works unlikely to be publicly acknowledged. For this reason, a study of publishing would be much more fruitful for discerning reading habits.[201] Across continental Europe, but in France especially, booksellers and publishers had to negotiate censorship laws of varying strictness. For example, the Encyclopédie narrowly escaped seizure and had to be saved by Malesherbes, the man in charge of the French censor. Indeed, many publishing companies were conveniently located outside France so as to avoid overzealous French censors. They would smuggle their merchandise across the border, where it would then be transported to clandestine booksellers or small-time peddlers.[202] The records of clandestine booksellers may give a better representation of what literate Frenchmen might have truly read, since their clandestine nature provided a less restrictive product choice.[203] In one case, political books were the most popular category, primarily libels and pamphlets. Readers were more interested in sensationalist stories about criminals and political corruption than they were in political theory itself. The second most popular category, «general works» (those books «that did not have a dominant motif and that contained something to offend almost everyone in authority»), demonstrated a high demand for generally low-brow subversive literature. However, these works never became part of literary canon and are largely forgotten today as a result.[203]

A healthy, legal publishing industry existed throughout Europe, although established publishers and book sellers occasionally ran afoul of the law. For example, the Encyclopédie condemned by both the King and Clement XII, nevertheless found its way into print with the help of the aforementioned Malesherbes and creative use of French censorship law.[204] However, many works were sold without running into any legal trouble at all. Borrowing records from libraries in England, Germany, and North America indicate that more than 70% of books borrowed were novels. Less than 1% of the books were of a religious nature, indicating the general trend of declining religiosity.[181]

Natural history[edit]

Georges Buffon is best remembered for his Histoire naturelle, a 44 volume encyclopedia describing everything known about the natural world

A genre that greatly rose in importance was that of scientific literature. Natural history in particular became increasingly popular among the upper classes. Works of natural history include René-Antoine Ferchault de Réaumur’s Histoire naturelle des insectes and Jacques Gautier d’Agoty’s La Myologie complète, ou description de tous les muscles du corps humain (1746). Outside Ancien Régime France, natural history was an important part of medicine and industry, encompassing the fields of botany, zoology, meteorology, hydrology, and mineralogy. Students in Enlightenment universities and academies were taught these subjects to prepare them for careers as diverse as medicine and theology. As shown by Matthew Daniel Eddy, natural history in this context was a very middle class pursuit and operated as a fertile trading zone for the interdisciplinary exchange of diverse scientific ideas.[205]

The target audience of natural history was French upper class, evidenced more by the specific discourse of the genre than by the generally high prices of its works. Naturalists catered to upper class desire for erudition: many texts had an explicit instructive purpose. However, natural history was often a political affair. As Emma Spary writes, the classifications used by naturalists «slipped between the natural world and the social … to establish not only the expertise of the naturalists over the natural, but also the dominance of the natural over the social».[206] The idea of taste (le goût) was a social indicator: to truly be able to categorize nature, one had to have the proper taste, an ability of discretion shared by all members of the upper class. In this way, natural history spread many of the scientific developments of the time but also provided a new source of legitimacy for the dominant class.[207] From this basis, naturalists could then develop their own social ideals based on their scientific works.[208]

Scientific and literary journals[edit]

The first scientific and literary journals were established during the Enlightenment. The first journal, the Parisian Journal des sçavans, appeared in 1665. However, it was not until 1682 that periodicals began to be more widely produced. French and Latin were the dominant languages of publication, but there was also a steady demand for material in German and Dutch. There was generally low demand for English publications on the continent, which was echoed by England’s similar lack of desire for French works. Languages commanding less of an international market—such as Danish, Spanish, and Portuguese—found journal success more difficult, and a more international language was used instead. French slowly took over Latin’s status as the lingua franca of learned circles. This in turn gave precedence to the publishing industry in Holland, where the vast majority of these French language periodicals were produced.[209]

Jonathan Israel called the journals the most influential cultural innovation of European intellectual culture.[210] They shifted the attention of the «cultivated public» away from established authorities to novelty and innovation, and instead promoted the Enlightened ideals of toleration and intellectual objectivity. Being a source of knowledge derived from science and reason, they were an implicit critique of existing notions of universal truth monopolized by monarchies, parliaments, and religious authorities. They also advanced Christian Enlightenment that upheld «the legitimacy of God-ordained authority»—the Bible—in which there had to be agreement between the biblical and natural theories.[211]

Encyclopedias and dictionaries[edit]

First page of the Encyclopédie, published between 1751 and 1766

Although the existence of dictionaries and encyclopedias spanned into ancient times, the texts changed from defining words in a long running list to far more detailed discussions of those words in 18th-century encyclopedic dictionaries.[212] The works were part of an Enlightenment movement to systematize knowledge and provide education to a wider audience than the elite. As the 18th century progressed, the content of encyclopedias also changed according to readers’ tastes. Volumes tended to focus more strongly on secular affairs, particularly science and technology, rather than matters of theology.

Along with secular matters, readers also favoured an alphabetical ordering scheme over cumbersome works arranged along thematic lines.[213] Commenting on alphabetization, the historian Charles Porset has said that «as the zero degree of taxonomy, alphabetical order authorizes all reading strategies; in this respect it could be considered an emblem of the Enlightenment». For Porset, the avoidance of thematic and hierarchical systems thus allows free interpretation of the works and becomes an example of egalitarianism.[214] Encyclopedias and dictionaries also became more popular during the Age of Enlightenment as the number of educated consumers who could afford such texts began to multiply.[212] In the latter half of the 18th century, the number of dictionaries and encyclopedias published by decade increased from 63 between 1760 and 1769 to approximately 148 in the decade proceeding the French Revolution.[215] Along with growth in numbers, dictionaries and encyclopedias also grew in length, often having multiple print runs that sometimes included in supplemented editions.[213]

The first technical dictionary was drafted by John Harris and entitled Lexicon Technicum: Or, An Universal English Dictionary of Arts and Sciences. Harris’ book avoids theological and biographical entries and instead concentrates on science and technology. Published in 1704, the Lexicon Technicum was the first book to be written in English that took a methodical approach to describing mathematics and commercial arithmetic along with the physical sciences and navigation. Other technical dictionaries followed Harris’ model, including Ephraim Chambers’ Cyclopaedia (1728), which included five editions and is a substantially larger work than Harris’. The folio edition of the work even included foldout engravings. The Cyclopaedia emphasized Newtonian theories, Lockean philosophy and contained thorough examinations of technologies, such as engraving, brewing, and dyeing.

In Germany, practical reference works intended for the uneducated majority became popular in the 18th century. The Marperger Curieuses Natur-, Kunst-, Berg-, Gewerk- und Handlungs-Lexicon (1712) explained terms that usefully described the trades and scientific and commercial education. Jablonksi Allgemeines Lexicon (1721) was better known than the Handlungs-Lexicon and underscored technical subjects rather than scientific theory. For example, over five columns of text were dedicated to wine while geometry and logic were allocated only twenty-two and seventeen lines, respectively. The first edition of the Encyclopædia Britannica (1771) was modelled along the same lines as the German lexicons.[216]

However, the prime example of reference works that systematized scientific knowledge in the Age of Enlightenment were universal encyclopedias rather than technical dictionaries. It was the goal of universal encyclopedias to record all human knowledge in a comprehensive reference work.[217] The most well-known of these works is Diderot and d’Alembert’s Encyclopédie, ou dictionnaire raisonné des sciences, des arts et des métiers. The work, which began publication in 1751, was composed of 35 volumes and over 71,000 separate entries. A great number of the entries were dedicated to describing the sciences and crafts in detail and provided intellectuals across Europe with a high-quality survey of human knowledge. In d’Alembert’s Preliminary Discourse to the Encyclopedia of Diderot, the work’s goal to record the extent of human knowledge in the arts and sciences is outlined:

As an Encyclopédie, it is to set forth as well as possible the order and connection of the parts of human knowledge. As a Reasoned Dictionary of the Sciences, Arts, and Trades, it is to contain the general principles that form the basis of each science and each art, liberal or mechanical, and the most essential facts that make up the body and substance of each.[218]

The massive work was arranged according to a «tree of knowledge». The tree reflected the marked division between the arts and sciences, which was largely a result of the rise of empiricism. Both areas of knowledge were united by philosophy, or the trunk of the tree of knowledge. The Enlightenment’s desacrilization of religion was pronounced in the tree’s design, particularly where theology accounted for a peripheral branch, with black magic as a close neighbour.[219] As the Encyclopédie gained popularity, it was published in quarto and octavo editions after 1777. The quarto and octavo editions were much less expensive than previous editions, making the Encyclopédie more accessible to the non-elite. Robert Darnton estimates that there were approximately 25,000 copies of the Encyclopédie in circulation throughout France and Europe before the French Revolution.[220] The extensive yet affordable encyclopedia came to represent the transmission of Enlightenment and scientific education to an expanding audience.[221]

Popularization of science[edit]

One of the most important developments that the Enlightenment era brought to the discipline of science was its popularization. An increasingly literate population seeking knowledge and education in both the arts and the sciences drove the expansion of print culture and the dissemination of scientific learning. The new literate population was precipitated by a high rise in the availability of food; this enabled many people to rise out of poverty, and instead of paying more for food, they had money for education.[222] Popularization was generally part of an overarching Enlightenment ideal that endeavoured «to make information available to the greatest number of people».[223] As public interest in natural philosophy grew during the 18th century, public lecture courses and the publication of popular texts opened up new roads to money and fame for amateurs and scientists who remained on the periphery of universities and academies.[224] More formal works included explanations of scientific theories for individuals lacking the educational background to comprehend the original scientific text. Newton’s celebrated Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica was published in Latin and remained inaccessible to readers without education in the classics until Enlightenment writers began to translate and analyze the text in the vernacular.

The first significant work that expressed scientific theory and knowledge expressly for the laity, in the vernacular and with the entertainment of readers in mind, was Bernard de Fontenelle’s Conversations on the Plurality of Worlds (1686). The book was produced specifically for women with an interest in scientific writing and inspired a variety of similar works.[225] These popular works were written in a discursive style, which was laid out much more clearly for the reader than the complicated articles, treatises, and books published by the academies and scientists. Charles Leadbetter’s Astronomy (1727) was advertised as «a Work entirely New» that would include «short and easie [sic] Rules and Astronomical Tables».[226]

The first French introduction to Newtonianism and the Principia was Eléments de la philosophie de Newton, published by Voltaire in 1738.[227] Émilie du Châtelet’s translation of the Principia, published after her death in 1756, also helped to spread Newton’s theories beyond scientific academies and the university.[228] Writing for a growing female audience, Francesco Algarotti published Il Newtonianism per le dame, which was a tremendously popular work and was translated from Italian into English by Elizabeth Carter. A similar introduction to Newtonianism for women was produced by Henry Pemberton. His A View of Sir Isaac Newton’s Philosophy was published by subscription. Extant records of subscribers show that women from a wide range of social standings purchased the book, indicating the growing number of scientifically inclined female readers among the middling class.[229] During the Enlightenment, women also began producing popular scientific works. Sarah Trimmer wrote a successful natural history textbook for children titled The Easy Introduction to the Knowledge of Nature (1782), which was published for many years in eleven editions.[230]

Schools and universities[edit]

Most work on the Enlightenment emphasizes the ideals discussed by intellectuals, rather than the actual state of education at the time. Leading educational theorists like England’s John Locke and Switzerland’s Jean Jacques Rousseau both emphasized the importance of shaping young minds early. By the late Enlightenment, there was a rising demand for a more universal approach to education, particularly after the American Revolution and the French Revolution.

The predominant educational psychology from the 1750s onward, especially in northern European countries, was associationism: the notion that the mind associates or dissociates ideas through repeated routines. In addition to being conducive to Enlightenment ideologies of liberty, self-determination, and personal responsibility, it offered a practical theory of the mind that allowed teachers to transform longstanding forms of print and manuscript culture into effective graphic tools of learning for the lower and middle orders of society.[231] Children were taught to memorize facts through oral and graphic methods that originated during the Renaissance.[232]

Many of the leading universities associated with Enlightenment progressive principles were located in northern Europe, with the most renowned being the universities of Leiden, Göttingen, Halle, Montpellier, Uppsala, and Edinburgh. These universities, especially Edinburgh, produced professors whose ideas had a significant impact on Britain’s North American colonies and later the American Republic. Within the natural sciences, Edinburgh’s medical school also led the way in chemistry, anatomy, and pharmacology.[233] In other parts of Europe, the universities and schools of France and most of Europe were bastions of traditionalism and were not hospitable to the Enlightenment. In France, the major exception was the medical university at Montpellier.[234]

Learned academies[edit]

Louis XIV visiting the Académie des sciences in 1671: «It is widely accepted that ‘modern science’ arose in the Europe of the 17th century, introducing a new understanding of the natural world»—Peter Barrett[235]

Antoine Lavoisier conducting an experiment related to combustion generated by amplified sun light

The history of Academies in France during the Enlightenment begins with the Academy of Science, founded in 1635 in Paris. It was closely tied to the French state, acting as an extension of a government seriously lacking in scientists. It helped promote and organize new disciplines and it trained new scientists. It also contributed to the enhancement of scientists’ social status, considering them to be the «most useful of all citizens». Academies demonstrate the rising interest in science along with its increasing secularization, as evidenced by the small number of clerics who were members (13%).[236] The presence of the French academies in the public sphere cannot be attributed to their membership, as although the majority of their members were bourgeois, the exclusive institution was only open to elite Parisian scholars. They perceived themselves as «interpreters of the sciences for the people». For example, it was with this in mind that academicians took it upon themselves to disprove the popular pseudo-science of mesmerism.[237]

The strongest contribution of the French Academies to the public sphere comes from the concours académiques (roughly translated as «academic contests») they sponsored throughout France. These academic contests were perhaps the most public of any institution during the Enlightenment.[238] The practice of contests dated back to the Middle Ages and was revived in the mid-17th century. The subject matter had previously been generally religious and/or monarchical, featuring essays, poetry, and painting. However, by roughly 1725 this subject matter had radically expanded and diversified, including «royal propaganda, philosophical battles, and critical ruminations on the social and political institutions of the Old Regime». Topics of public controversy were also discussed such as the theories of Newton and Descartes, the slave trade, women’s education, and justice in France.[239] More importantly, the contests were open to all, and the enforced anonymity of each submission guaranteed that neither gender nor social rank would determine the judging. Indeed, although the «vast majority» of participants belonged to the wealthier strata of society («the liberal arts, the clergy, the judiciary and the medical profession»), there were some cases of the popular classes submitting essays and even winning.[240] Similarly, a significant number of women participated—and won—the competitions. Of a total of 2,300 prize competitions offered in France, women won 49—perhaps a small number by modern standards but very significant in an age in which most women did not have any academic training. Indeed, the majority of the winning entries were for poetry competitions, a genre commonly stressed in women’s education.[241]

In England, the Royal Society of London played a significant role in the public sphere and the spread of Enlightenment ideas. It was founded by a group of independent scientists and given a royal charter in 1662.[242] The society played a large role in spreading Robert Boyle’s experimental philosophy around Europe and acted as a clearinghouse for intellectual correspondence and exchange.[243] Boyle was «a founder of the experimental world in which scientists now live and operate» and his method based knowledge on experimentation, which had to be witnessed to provide proper empirical legitimacy. This is where the Royal Society came into play: witnessing had to be a «collective act» and the Royal Society’s assembly rooms were ideal locations for relatively public demonstrations.[244] However, not just any witness was considered to be credible: «Oxford professors were accounted more reliable witnesses than Oxfordshire peasants». Two factors were taken into account: a witness’s knowledge in the area and a witness’s «moral constitution». In other words, only civil society were considered for Boyle’s public.[245]

Salons[edit]

Salons were places where philosophes were reunited and discussed old, actual, or new ideas. This led to salons being the birthplace of intellectual and enlightened ideas.

Coffeehouses[edit]

Coffeehouses were especially important to the spread of knowledge during the Enlightenment because they created a unique environment in which people from many different walks of life gathered and shared ideas. They were frequently criticized by nobles who feared the possibility of an environment in which class and its accompanying titles and privileges were disregarded. Such an environment was especially intimidating to monarchs who derived much of their power from the disparity between classes of people. If classes were to join under the influence of Enlightenment thinking, they might recognize the all-encompassing oppression and abuses of their monarchs and because of their size might be able to carry out successful revolts. Monarchs also resented the idea of their subjects convening as one to discuss political matters, especially those concerning foreign affairs—rulers thought political affairs to be their business only, a result of their supposed divine right to rule.[246]

Coffeeshops became homes away from home for many who sought to engage in discourse with their neighbors and discuss intriguing and thought-provoking matters, especially those regarding philosophy to politics. Coffeehouses were essential to the Enlightenment, for they were centers of free-thinking and self-discovery. Although many coffeehouse patrons were scholars, a great deal were not. Coffeehouses attracted a diverse set of people, including the educated wealthy and members of the bourgeoisie and the lower class. While it may seem positive that patrons, being doctors, lawyers, merchants, etc. represented almost all classes, the coffeeshop environment sparked fear in those who sought to preserve class distinction. One of the most popular critiques of the coffeehouse claimed that it «allowed promiscuous association among people from different rungs of the social ladder, from the artisan to the aristocrat» and was therefore compared to Noah’s Ark, receiving all types of animals, clean or unclean.[247] This unique culture served as a catalyst for journalism when Joseph Addison and Richard Steele recognized its potential as an audience. Together, Steele and Addison published The Spectator (1711), a daily publication which aimed, through fictional narrator Mr. Spectator, both to entertain and to provoke discussion regarding serious philosophical matters.

The first English coffeehouse opened in Oxford in 1650. Brian Cowan said that Oxford coffeehouses developed into «penny universities», offering a locus of learning that was less formal than structured institutions. These penny universities occupied a significant position in Oxford academic life, as they were frequented by those consequently referred to as the virtuosi, who conducted their research on some of the resulting premises. According to Cowan, «the coffeehouse was a place for like-minded scholars to congregate, to read, as well as learn from and to debate with each other, but was emphatically not a university institution, and the discourse there was of a far different order than any university tutorial».[248]

The Café Procope was established in Paris in 1686, and by the 1720s there were around 400 cafés in the city. The Café Procope in particular became a center of Enlightenment, welcoming such celebrities as Voltaire and Rousseau. The Café Procope was where Diderot and D’Alembert decided to create the Encyclopédie.[249] The cafés were one of the various «nerve centers» for bruits publics, public noise or rumour. These bruits were allegedly a much better source of information than were the actual newspapers available at the time.[250]

Debating societies[edit]

The debating societies are an example of the public sphere during the Enlightenment.[251] Their origins include:

  • Clubs of fifty or more men who, at the beginning of the 18th century, met in pubs to discuss religious issues and affairs of state.
  • Mooting clubs, set up by law students to practice rhetoric.
  • Spouting clubs, established to help actors train for theatrical roles.
  • John Henley’s Oratory, which mixed outrageous sermons with even more absurd questions, like «Whether Scotland be anywhere in the world?».[252]

An example of a French salon

In the late 1770s, popular debating societies began to move into more «genteel» rooms, a change which helped establish a new standard of sociability.[253] The backdrop to these developments was «an explosion of interest in the theory and practice of public elocution». The debating societies were commercial enterprises that responded to this demand, sometimes very successfully. Some societies welcomed from 800 to 1,200 spectators per night.[254]

The debating societies discussed an extremely wide range of topics. Before the Enlightenment, most intellectual debates revolved around «confessional»—that is, Catholic, Lutheran, Reformed (Calvinist) or Anglican issues, and the main aim of these debates was to establish which bloc of faith ought to have the «monopoly of truth and a God-given title to authority».[255] After this date, everything thus previously rooted in tradition was questioned and often replaced by new concepts in the light of philosophical reason. After the second half of the 17th century and during the 18th century, a «general process of rationalization and secularization set in» and confessional disputes were reduced to a secondary status in favor of the «escalating contest between faith and incredulity».[255]

In addition to debates on religion, societies discussed issues such as politics and the role of women. However, the critical subject matter of these debates did not necessarily translate into opposition to the government; the results of the debate quite frequently upheld the status quo.[256] From a historical standpoint, one of the most important features of the debating society was their openness to the public, as women attended and even participated in almost every debating society, which were likewise open to all classes providing they could pay the entrance fee. Once inside, spectators were able to participate in a largely egalitarian form of sociability that helped spread Enlightenment ideas.[257]

Masonic lodges[edit]

Masonic initiation ceremony

Historians have long debated the extent to which the secret network of Freemasonry was a main factor in the Enlightenment.[258] The leaders of the Enlightenment included Freemasons such as Diderot, Montesquieu, Voltaire, Lessing, Pope,[259] Horace Walpole, Sir Robert Walpole, Mozart, Goethe, Frederick the Great, Benjamin Franklin[260] and George Washington.[261] Norman Davies said that Freemasonry was a powerful force on behalf of liberalism in Europe from about 1700 to the twentieth century. It expanded rapidly during the Age of Enlightenment, reaching practically every country in Europe. It was especially attractive to powerful aristocrats and politicians as well as intellectuals, artists, and political activists.[262]

During the Age of Enlightenment, Freemasons comprised an international network of like-minded men, often meeting in secret in ritualistic programs at their lodges. They promoted the ideals of the Enlightenment and helped diffuse these values across Britain, France, and other places. Freemasonry as a systematic creed with its own myths, values, and set of rituals originated in Scotland c. 1600 and spread first to England and then across the Continent in the eighteenth century. They fostered new codes of conduct—including a communal understanding of liberty and equality inherited from guild sociability—»liberty, fraternity, and equality».[263] Scottish soldiers and Jacobite Scots brought to the Continent ideals of fraternity which reflected not the local system of Scottish customs but the institutions and ideals originating in the English Revolution against royal absolutism.[264] Freemasonry was particularly prevalent in France—by 1789, there were perhaps as many as 100,000 French Masons, making Freemasonry the most popular of all Enlightenment associations.[265] The Freemasons displayed a passion for secrecy and created new degrees and ceremonies. Similar societies, partially imitating Freemasonry, emerged in France, Germany, Sweden, and Russia. One example was the Illuminati founded in Bavaria in 1776, which was copied after the Freemasons, but was never part of the movement. The Illuminati was an overtly political group, which most Masonic lodges decidedly were not.[266]

Masonic lodges created a private model for public affairs. They «reconstituted the polity and established a constitutional form of self-government, complete with constitutions and laws, elections, and representatives». In other words, the micro-society set up within the lodges constituted a normative model for society as a whole. This was especially true on the continent: when the first lodges began to appear in the 1730s, their embodiment of British values was often seen as threatening by state authorities. For example, the Parisian lodge that met in the mid 1720s was composed of English Jacobite exiles.[267] Furthermore, freemasons all across Europe explicitly linked themselves to the Enlightenment as a whole. For example, in French lodges the line «As the means to be enlightened I search for the enlightened» was a part of their initiation rites. British lodges assigned themselves the duty to «initiate the unenlightened». This did not necessarily link lodges to the irreligious, but neither did this exclude them from the occasional heresy. In fact, many lodges praised the Grand Architect, the masonic terminology for the deistic divine being who created a scientifically ordered universe.[268]

German historian Reinhart Koselleck claimed: «On the Continent there were two social structures that left a decisive imprint on the Age of Enlightenment: the Republic of Letters and the Masonic lodges».[269] Scottish professor Thomas Munck argues that «although the Masons did promote international and cross-social contacts which were essentially non-religious and broadly in agreement with enlightened values, they can hardly be described as a major radical or reformist network in their own right».[270] Many of the Masons values seemed to greatly appeal to Enlightenment values and thinkers. Diderot discusses the link between Freemason ideals and the enlightenment in D’Alembert’s Dream, exploring masonry as a way of spreading enlightenment beliefs.[271] Historian Margaret Jacob stresses the importance of the Masons in indirectly inspiring enlightened political thought.[272] On the negative side, Daniel Roche contests claims that Masonry promoted egalitarianism and he argues that the lodges only attracted men of similar social backgrounds.[273] The presence of noble women in the French «lodges of adoption» that formed in the 1780s was largely due to the close ties shared between these lodges and aristocratic society.[274]

The major opponent of Freemasonry was the Roman Catholic Church so that in countries with a large Catholic element, such as France, Italy, Spain, and Mexico, much of the ferocity of the political battles involve the confrontation between what Davies calls the reactionary Church and enlightened Freemasonry.[275][276] Even in France, Masons did not act as a group.[277] American historians, while noting that Benjamin Franklin and George Washington were indeed active Masons, have downplayed the importance of Freemasonry in causing the American Revolution because the Masonic order was non-political and included both Patriots and their enemy the Loyalists.[278]

Art[edit]

The art produced during the Enlightenment focused on a search for morality that was absent from the art in previous eras.[citation needed] At the same time, the Classical art of Greece and Rome became interesting to people again, since archaeological teams discovered Pompeii and Herculaneum.[279] People took inspiration from it and revived classical art into neo-classical art. This can especially be seen in early American art and architecture, which featured arches, goddesses, and other classical architectural designs.

See also[edit]

  • Atlantic Revolutions
  • Early modern philosophy
  • European and American voyages of scientific exploration
  • Midlands Enlightenment
  • Regional Enlightenments:
    • American Enlightenment
    • Haskalah, Jewish Enlightenment
    • Modern Greek Enlightenment
    • Polish Enlightenment
    • Russian Enlightenment
    • Scottish Enlightenment
    • Spanish Enlightenment
  • Renaissance philosophy
  • Whig history
  • Witch trials in the early modern period
    • Beyond the witch trials

Notes[edit]

  1. ^ Back row, left to right: Jean-Baptiste-Louis Gresset, Pierre de Marivaux, Jean-François Marmontel, Joseph-Marie Vien, Antoine Léonard Thomas, Charles Marie de La Condamine, Guillaume Thomas François Raynal, Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Jean-Philippe Rameau, La Clairon, Charles-Jean-François Hénault, Étienne François, duc de Choiseul, a bust of Voltaire, Charles-Augustin de Ferriol d’Argental, Jean François de Saint-Lambert, Edmé Bouchardon, Jacques-Germain Soufflot, Jean-Baptiste Bourguignon d’Anville, Anne Claude de Caylus, Fortunato Felice, François Quesnay, Denis Diderot, Anne-Robert-Jacques Turgot, Baron de Laune, Chrétien Guillaume de Lamoignon de Malesherbes, Armand de Vignerot du Plessis, Pierre Louis Maupertuis, Jean-Jacques Dortous de Mairan, Henri François d’Aguesseau, Alexis Clairaut.
    Front row, right to left: Montesquieu, Sophie d’Houdetot, Claude Joseph Vernet, Bernard Le Bouyer de Fontenelle, Marie-Thérèse Rodet Geoffrin, Louis François, Prince of Conti, Marie Louise Nicole Élisabeth de La Rochefoucauld, Duchesse d’Anville, Philippe Jules François Mancini, François-Joachim de Pierre de Bernis, Claude Prosper Jolyot de Crébillon, Alexis Piron, Charles Pinot Duclos, Claude-Adrien Helvétius, Charles-André van Loo, Jean le Rond d’Alembert, Lekain at the desk reading aloud, Jeanne Julie Éléonore de Lespinasse, Anne-Marie du Boccage, René Antoine Ferchault de Réaumur, Françoise de Graffigny, Étienne Bonnot de Condillac, Bernard de Jussieu, Louis-Jean-Marie Daubenton, Georges-Louis Charles Leclerc, Comte de Buffon.
  2. ^ French: le Siècle des Lumières, lit. ‘the Century of Lights’; German: Aufklärung, «Enlightenment»; Italian: L’Illuminismo, «Enlightenment»; Polish: Oświecenie, «Enlightenment»; Portuguese: Iluminismo, «Enlightenment»; Spanish: La Ilustración, «Enlightenment»[1]
  3. ^ For example, Robert Darnton, Roger Chartier, Brian Cowan, Donna T. Andrew.

References[edit]

Citations[edit]

  1. ^ «Enlightenment», Encyclopædia Britannica, Encyclopædia Britannica Online, Encyclopædia Britannica Inc., 2016, retrieved 13 June 2016
  2. ^ «The Age of Enlightenment: A History From Beginning to chop and daisy mwah Chapter 3». publishinghau5.com. Archived from the original on 3 March 2017. Retrieved 3 April 2017.{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: unfit URL (link)
  3. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p q r s t u v w x y z aa ab Conrad, Sebastian (1 October 2012). «Enlightenment in Global History: A Historiographical Critique». The American Historical Review. 117 (4): 999–1027. doi:10.1093/ahr/117.4.999. ISSN 0002-8762.
  4. ^ Outram, Dorinda (2006), Panorama of the Enlightenment, Getty Publications, p. 29, ISBN 978-0892368617
  5. ^ Zafirovski, Milan (2010), The Enlightenment and Its Effects on Modern Society, p. 144
  6. ^ a b Rashidov, Zaur (15 December 2022). «The philosophy of Azerbaijan Enlightenment in the studies of Enver Akhmedov: a critical analysis» (PDF). Metafizika Journal (in Azerbaijani). 5 (4): 54–76. eISSN 2617-751X. ISSN 2616-6879. OCLC 1117709579. Archived from the original (PDF) on 28 January 2023. Retrieved 14 October 2022.{{cite journal}}: CS1 maint: date and year (link)
  7. ^ Eugen Weber, Movements, Currents, Trends: Aspects of European Thought in the Nineteenth and Twentieth Centuries (1992).
  8. ^ Eddy, Matthew Daniel (2022). Media and the Mind: Art, Science and Notebooks as Paper Machines, 1700-1830. University of Chicago Press.
  9. ^ Gay, Peter (1996), The Enlightenment: An Interpretation, W.W. Norton & Company, ISBN 0-393-00870-3
  10. ^ Vottari, Giuseppe (2003). L’illuminismo. Un percorso alfabetico nell’età delle riforme. Alpha Test. p. 54. ISBN 978-88-483-0456-6.
  11. ^ Maddaloni, Domenico (17 November 2011). Visioni in movimento. Teorie dell’evoluzione e scienze sociali dall’Illuminismo a oggi: Teorie dell’evoluzione e scienze sociali dall’Illuminismo a oggi. FrancoAngeli. p. 20. ISBN 978-88-568-7115-9.
  12. ^ I. Bernard Cohen, «Scientific Revolution and Creativity in the Enlightenment.» Eighteenth-Century Life 7.2 (1982): 41–54.
  13. ^ Sootin, Harry. Isaac Newton. New York: Messner (1955)
  14. ^ a b Jeremy Black, «Ancien Regime and Enlightenment. Some Recent Writing on Seventeenth-and Eighteenth-Century Europe,» European History Quarterly 22.2 (1992): 247–55.
  15. ^ Robert Darnton, The Business of Enlightenment: a publishing history of the Encyclopédie, 1775–1800 (2009).
  16. ^ The Dream of Enlightenment: The Rise of Modern Philosophy. W. W. Norton & Company. 30 August 2016. ISBN 9781631492082.
  17. ^ Israel 2006, p. 15.
  18. ^ Israel 2010, pp. vii–viii, 19.
  19. ^ Israel 2010, p. 11.
  20. ^ «Enlightenment – Definition, History, & Facts». Encyclopedia Britannica.
  21. ^ a b Petitfils 2005, pp. 99–105.
  22. ^ a b Denby, David (11 October 2004), «Northern Lights: How modern life emerged from eighteenth-century Edinburgh», The New Yorker, archived from the original on 6 June 2011
  23. ^ Barroso, José Manuel (28 November 2006), The Scottish enlightenment and the challenges for Europe in the 21st century; climate change and energy
  24. ^ «Kant’s essay What is Enlightenment?». mnstate.edu. Archived from the original on 17 February 2020. Retrieved 4 November 2015.
  25. ^ Manfred Kuehn, Kant: A Biography (2001).
  26. ^ Kreis, Steven (13 April 2012). «Mary Wollstonecraft, 1759–1797». Historyguide.org. Archived from the original on 11 January 2014. Retrieved 14 January 2014.
  27. ^ Mary Wollstonecraft, A Vindication of the Rights of Woman (Renascence Editions, 2000) online
  28. ^ Bruce P. Lenman, Integration and Enlightenment: Scotland, 1746–1832 (1993) excerpt and text search
  29. ^ Sarmant, Thierry, Histoire de Paris, p. 120.
  30. ^ Porter (2003), 79–80.
  31. ^ Burns (2003), entry: 7,103.
  32. ^ Gillispie, (1980), p. xix.
  33. ^ James E. McClellan III, «Learned Societies,» in Encyclopedia of the Enlightenment, ed. Alan Charles Kors (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003) «Oxford University Press: Encyclopedia of the Enlightenment: Alan Charles Kors». Archived from the original on 30 March 2012. Retrieved 16 October 2015. (accessed on 8 June 2008).
  34. ^ Porter, (2003), p. 91.
  35. ^ See Gillispie, (1980), «Conclusion.»
  36. ^ Porter, (2003), p. 90.
  37. ^ see Hall (1954), iii; Mason (1956), 223.
  38. ^ Burns, (2003), entry: 158.
  39. ^ Thomson, (1786), p. 203.
  40. ^ M. Magnusson (10 November 2003), «Review of James Buchan, Capital of the Mind: how Edinburgh Changed the World«, New Statesman, archived from the original on 6 June 2011, retrieved 27 April 2014
  41. ^ Swingewood, Alan (1970). «Origins of Sociology: The Case of the Scottish Enlightenment». The British Journal of Sociology. 21 (2): 164–180. doi:10.2307/588406. JSTOR 588406.
  42. ^ D. Daiches, P. Jones and J. Jones, A Hotbed of Genius: The Scottish Enlightenment, 1730–1790 (1986).
  43. ^ M. Fry, Adam Smith’s Legacy: His Place in the Development of Modern Economics (Routledge, 1992).
  44. ^ The Illusion of Free Markets, Bernard E. Harcourt, p. 260, notes 11–14.
  45. ^ «The Enlightenment throughout Europe». History-world.org. Archived from the original on 23 January 2013. Retrieved 25 March 2013.{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: unfit URL (link)
  46. ^ Roland Sarti, Italy: A Reference Guide from the Renaissance to the Present, Infobase Publishing, 2009, p. 457
  47. ^ Daniel Brewer, The Enlightenment Past: reconstructing eighteenth-century French thought (2008), p. 1
  48. ^ De Dijn, Annelien (2012). «The Politics of Enlightenment: From Peter Gay to Jonathan Israel». Historical Journal. 55 (3): 785–805. doi:10.1017/s0018246x12000301. S2CID 145439970.
  49. ^ von Guttner, Darius (2015). The French Revolution. Nelson Cengage. pp. 34–35.[permanent dead link]
  50. ^ Robert A. Ferguson, The American Enlightenment, 1750–1820 (1994).
  51. ^ «John Locke > The Influence of John Locke’s Works (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)». Plato.stanford.edu. Retrieved 14 January 2014.
  52. ^ Pierre Manent, An Intellectual History of Liberalism (1994) pp. 20–38
  53. ^ Lessnoff, Michael H. Social Contract Theory. New York: NYU, 1990. Print.[page needed]
  54. ^ Discourse on the Origin of Inequality
  55. ^ Rand, B. (1900), The Life, Unpublished Letters and Philosophical Regimen of Anthony, Earl of Shaftesbury, p. 353 quoted in Porter, Roy (2000), Enlightenment, Britain and the Creation of the Modern World, Allen Lane, The Penguin Press, p. 3
  56. ^ Lorraine Y. Landry, Marx and the postmodernism debates: an agenda for critical theory (2000) p. 7
  57. ^ Of the Original Contract
  58. ^ Eltis, David; Walvin, James, eds. (1981). The Abolition of the Atlantic Slave Trade. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press. p. 76.
  59. ^ Northrup, David, ed. (2002). The Atlantic Slave Trade. Boston: Houghton Mifflin. p. 200.
  60. ^ David Williams, ed. (1994). Voltaire: Political Writings. pp. xiv–xv. ISBN 978-0-521-43727-1.
  61. ^ Stephen J. Lee, Aspects of European history, 1494–1789 (1990) pp. 258–266
  62. ^ Nicholas Henderson, «Joseph II», History Today (March 1991) 41:21–27
  63. ^ John Stanley, «Towards A New Nation: The Enlightenment and National Revival in Poland», Canadian Review of Studies in Nationalism, 1983, Vol. 10 Issue 2, pp. 83–110
  64. ^ Giles MacDonogh, Frederick the Great: A Life in Deed and Letters (2001) p. 341
  65. ^ «Enlightenment ideals of rationalism and intellectual and religious freedom pervaded the American colonial religious landscape, and these values were instrumental in the American Revolution and the creation of a nation without an established religion». Enlightenment and Revolution, Pluralism Project, Harvard University.
  66. ^ Fremont-Barnes, Gregory (2007). Encyclopedia of the Age of Political Revolutions and New Ideologies, 1760–1815. Greenwood. p. 190. ISBN 9780313049514.
  67. ^ «Recognized in Europe as the author of the Declaration of Independence, Thomas Jefferson quickly became a focal point or lightning rod for revolutionaries in Europe and the Americas. As United States minister to France when revolutionary fervor was rising toward the storming of the Bastille in 1789, Jefferson became an ardent supporter of the French Revolution, even allowing his residence to be used as a meeting place for the rebels led by Lafayette». Thomas Jefferson. A Revolutionary World. Library of Congress.
  68. ^ Chartier, 8. See also Alexis de Tocqueville, L’Ancien Régime et la Révolution, 1850, Book Three, Chapter One.
  69. ^ Chartier, 13.
  70. ^ A Treatise on Toleration
  71. ^ Margaret C. Jacob, ed. The Enlightenment: Brief History with Documents, Boston: Bedford/St. Martin’s, 2001, Introduction, pp. 1–72.
  72. ^ Locke, John (1695). Reasonableness of Christianity. Vol. «Preface» The Reasonableness of Christianity, as delivered in the Scriptures.
  73. ^ R.B. Bernstein (2003). Thomas Jefferson. Oxford University Press. p. 179. ISBN 978-0-19-975844-9.
  74. ^ Ole Peter Grell; Porter, Roy (2000). Toleration in Enlightenment Europe. Cambridge University Press. pp. 1–68. ISBN 978-0-521-65196-7.
  75. ^ Baruch Spinoza, Theologico-Political Treatise, «Preface,» 1677, gutenberg.com
  76. ^ Mendelssohn, Moses (1783). «Jerusalem: Or on Religious Power and Judaism» (PDF).
  77. ^ Goetschel, Willi (2004). Spinoza’s Modernity: Mendelssohn, Lessing, and Heine. Univ of Wisconsin Press. p. 126. ISBN 978-0-299-19083-5.
  78. ^ Thomas Paine, Of the Religion of Deism Compared with the Christian Religion, 1804, Internet History Sourcebook
  79. ^ Ellen Judy Wilson; Peter Hanns Reill (2004). Encyclopedia Of The Enlightenment. Infobase Publishing. p. 148. ISBN 978-1-4381-1021-9.
  80. ^ Wilson and Reill (2004). Encyclopedia Of The Enlightenment. Infobase Publishing. p. 26. ISBN 978-1-4381-1021-9.
  81. ^ Pagden, Anthony (2013). The Enlightenment: And Why it Still Matters. Oxford University Press. p. 100. ISBN 978-0-19-966093-3.
  82. ^ Brown, Stuart (2003). British Philosophy and the Age of Enlightenment: Routledge History of Philosophy. Taylor & Francis. p. 256. ISBN 978-0-415-30877-9.
  83. ^ Bayle, Pierre (1741). A general dictionary: historical and critical: in which a new and accurate translation of that of the celebrated Mr. Bayle, with the corrections and observations printed in the late edition at Paris, is included; and interspersed with several thousand lives never before published. The whole containing the history of the most illustrious persons of all ages and nations particularly those of Great Britain and Ireland, distinguished by their rank, actions, learning and other accomplishments. With reflections on such passages of Bayle, as seem to favor scepticism and the Manichee system. p. 778.
  84. ^ ENR // AgencyND // University of Notre Dame (4 May 2003). «God, Locke and Equality: Christian Foundations of Locke’s Political Thought». Nd.edu.
  85. ^ Israel 2011, pp. 11.
  86. ^ Israel 2010, p. 19.
  87. ^ Israel 2010, pp. vii–viii.
  88. ^ Feldman, Noah (2005). Divided by God. Farrar, Straus, and Giroux, p. 29 («It took John Locke to translate the demand for liberty of conscience into a systematic argument for distinguishing the realm of government from the realm of religion.»)
  89. ^ Feldman, Noah (2005). Divided by God. Farrar, Straus, and Giroux, p. 29
  90. ^ Ferling, 2000, p. 158
  91. ^ Mayer, 1994 p. 76
  92. ^ Hayes, 2008, p. 10
  93. ^ Cogliano, 2003, p. 14
  94. ^ David N. Livingstone and Charles W.J. Withers, Geography and Enlightenment (1999)
  95. ^ a b A History of Modern Latin America: 1800 to the Present, Second Edition, by Teresa A. Meade
  96. ^ Peter Gay, ed. The Enlightenment: A comprehensive anthology (1973) p. 14
  97. ^ Roy Porter, «England» in Alan Charles Kors, ed., Encyclopedia of the Enlightenment (2003) 1:409–15.
  98. ^ Karen O’Brien, «English Enlightenment Histories, 1750–c.1815» in José Rabasa, ed. (2012). The Oxford History of Historical Writing: Volume 3: 1400–1800. Oxford, England: OUP. pp. 518–535. ISBN 978-0-19-921917-9.
  99. ^ Roy Porter, The creation of the modern world: the untold story of the British Enlightenment (2000), pp. 1–12, 482–484.
  100. ^ Eddy, Matthew Daniel (2022). Media and the Mind: Art, Science and Notebooks as Paper Machines, 1700-1830. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  101. ^ Towsey, Mark (2010). Reading the Scottish Enlightenment Books and Their Readers in Provincial Scotland, 1750-1820. Brill. ISBN 9789004193512.
  102. ^ A. Herman, How the Scots Invented the Modern World (Crown Publishing Group, 2001).
  103. ^ Harrison, Lawrence E. (2012). Jews, Confucians, and Protestants: Cultural Capital and the End of Multiculturalism. Rowman & Littlefield. p. 92. ISBN 978-1-4422-1964-9.
  104. ^ J. Repcheck, The Man Who Found Time: James Hutton and the Discovery of the Earth’s Antiquity (Basic Books, 2003), pp. 117–143.
  105. ^ Henry F. May, The Enlightenment in America (1978)
  106. ^ Michael Atiyah, «Benjamin Franklin and the Edinburgh Enlightenment,» Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society (Dec 2006) 150#4 pp. 591–606.
  107. ^ Jack Fruchtman, Jr., Atlantic Cousins: Benjamin Franklin and His Visionary Friends (2007)
  108. ^ Charles C. Mann, 1491 (2005)
  109. ^ Paul M. Spurlin, Montesquieu in America, 1760–1801 (1941)
  110. ^ «The Founding Fathers, Deism, and Christianity». Encyclopædia Britannica.
  111. ^ Charles W. Ingrao, «A Pre-Revolutionary Sonderweg.» German History 20#3 (2002), pp. 279–286.
  112. ^ Katrin Keller, «Saxony: Rétablissement and Enlightened Absolutism.» German History 20.3 (2002): 309–331.
  113. ^ «The German Enlightenment», German History (Dec 2017) 35#4 pp. 588–602, round table discussion of historiography.
  114. ^ Gagliardo, John G. (1991). Germany under the Old Regime, 1600–1790. pp. 217–234, 375–395.
  115. ^ Richter, Simon J., ed. (2005), The Literature of Weimar Classicism
  116. ^ Owens, Samantha; Reul, Barbara M.; Stockigt, Janice B., eds. (2011). Music at German Courts, 1715–1760: Changing Artistic Priorities.
  117. ^ Kuehn, Manfred (2001). Kant: A Biography.
  118. ^ Van Dulmen, Richard; Williams, Anthony, eds. (1992). The Society of the Enlightenment: The Rise of the Middle Class and Enlightenment Culture in Germany.
  119. ^ Thomas P. Saine, The Problem of Being Modern, or the German Pursuit of Enlightenment from Leibniz to the French Revolution (1997)
  120. ^ Michael J. Sauter, «The Enlightenment on trial: state service and social discipline in eighteenth-century Germany’s public sphere.» Modern Intellectual History 5.2 (2008): 195–223.
  121. ^ Mori, Massimo (1 February 2015). Storia della filosofia moderna (in Italian). Gius.Laterza & Figli Spa. ISBN 978-88-581-1845-0.
  122. ^ D’Onofrio, Federico (2015). On the caoncept of ‘felicitas publica’ in Eighteenth-Century political economy, in History of economic thought.
  123. ^ Niccolò Guasti, «Antonio Genovesi’s Diceosina: Source of the Neapolitan Enlightenment.» History of European ideas 32.4 (2006): 385–405.
  124. ^ Pier Luigi Porta, «Lombard enlightenment and classical political economy.» The European Journal of the History of Economic Thought 18.4 (2011): 521–50.
  125. ^ Franco Venturi, Italy and the Enlightenment: studies in a cosmopolitan century (1972) online
  126. ^ Anna Maria Rao, «Enlightenment and reform: an overview of culture and politics in Enlightenment Italy.» Journal of Modern Italian Studies 10.2 (2005): 142–67.
  127. ^ Aldridge, Alfred Owen. The Ibero-American Enlightenment. Urbana: University of Illinois Press 1971.
  128. ^ De Vos, Paula S. «Research, Development, and Empire: State Support of Science in Spain and Spanish America, Sixteenth to Eighteenth Centuries,» Colonial Latin America Review 15, no. 1 (June 2006) 55–79.
  129. ^ Bleichmar, Daniela. Visible Empire: Botanical Expeditions & Visual Culture in the Hispanic Enlightenment. Chicago: University of Chicago Press 2012.
  130. ^ Brading, D. A. The First America: The Spanish Monarchy, Creole Patriots, and the Liberal State, 1492–1867 Chapter 23, «Scientific Traveller». New York: Cambridge University Press 1991 ISBN 0-521-39130-X
  131. ^ Thiessen, Heather. «Spain: Constitution of 1812.» Encyclopedia of Latin American History and Culture, vol. 5, p. 165. New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons 1996.
  132. ^ Cohen, Thomas M. (15 November 2018). «Six Sermons, written by António Vieira». Journal of Jesuit Studies. 5 (4): 692–695. doi:10.1163/22141332-00504010-11. ISSN 2214-1324.
  133. ^ Elise Kimerling Wirtschafter, «Thoughts on the Enlightenment and Enlightenment in Russia», Modern Russian History & Historiography, 2009, Vol. 2 Issue 2, pp. 1–26
  134. ^ Israel 2011, pp. 609–32.
  135. ^ Colum Leckey, «What is Prosveshchenie? Nikolai Novikov’s Historical Dictionary of Russian Writers Revisited.» Russian History 37.4 (2010): 360–77.
  136. ^ Maciej Janowski, «Warsaw and Its Intelligentsia: Urban Space and Social Change, 1750–1831.» Acta Poloniae Historica 100 (2009): 57–77. ISSN 0001-6829
  137. ^ Richard Butterwick, «What is Enlightenment (oświecenie)? Some Polish Answers, 1765–1820.» Central Europe 3.1 (2005): 19–37. online[dead link]
  138. ^ Jerzy Snopek, «The Polish Literature of the Enlightenment.» Archived 5 October 2011 at the Wayback Machine (PDF 122 KB) Poland.pl. Retrieved 7 October 2011.
  139. ^ Ronald P. Toby, State and Diplomacy in Early Modern Japan: Asia in the Development of the Tokugawa Bakufu, Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press, (1984) 1991.
  140. ^ Keith Thomas, «The Great Fight Over the Enlightenment,» The New York Review April 3, 2014
  141. ^ a b Thomas, 2014
  142. ^
    Ritchie Robertson, «The Enlightenment: The Pursuit of Happiness, 1680–1790.» (2020) ch. 1.
  143. ^ Oxford English Dictionary, 3rd Edn (revised)
  144. ^ Lough, John (1985). «Reflections on Enlightenment and Lumieres». Journal for Eighteenth-Century Studies. 8#1: 1–15. doi:10.1111/j.1754-0208.1985.tb00093.x.
  145. ^ Jean le Rond d’Alembert, Discours préliminaire de l’Encyclopédie
  146. ^ Outram, 1. The past tense is used deliberately as whether man would educate himself or be educated by certain exemplary figures was a common issue at the time. D’Alembert’s introduction to l’Encyclopédie, for example, along with Immanuel Kant’s essay response (the «independent thinkers»), both support the later model.
  147. ^ Immanuel Kant, «What is Enlightenment?», 1.
  148. ^ Porter 2001, p. 1
  149. ^ Ernst Cassirer, The Philosophy of the Enlightenment, (1951), p. vi
  150. ^ Porter 2001, p. 70
  151. ^ a b Russell, Bertrand. A History of Western Philosophy. pp. 492–494
  152. ^ Israel 2010, pp. 49–50.
  153. ^ Israel 2006, pp. v–viii.
  154. ^ Israel 2001, pp. 3.
  155. ^ Martin Heidegger [1938] (2002) The Age of the World Picture quotation:

    For up to Descartes … a particular sub-iectum … lies at the foundation of its own fixed qualities and changing circumstances. The superiority of a sub-iectum … arises out of the claim of man to a … self-supported, unshakeable foundation of truth, in the sense of certainty. Why and how does this claim acquire its decisive authority? The claim originates in that emancipation of man in which he frees himself from obligation to Christian revelational truth and Church doctrine to a legislating for himself that takes its stand upon itself.

  156. ^ Ingraffia, Brian D. (1995) Postmodern theory and biblical theology: vanquishing God’s shadow p. 126
  157. ^ Norman K. Swazo (2002) Crisis theory and world order: Heideggerian reflections pp. 97–99
  158. ^ Shank, J. B. The Newton Wars and the Beginning of the French Enlightenment (2008), «Introduction»[page needed]
  159. ^ «PHYS 200 – Lecture 3 – Newton’s Laws of Motion – Open Yale Courses». oyc.yale.edu.
  160. ^ Anderson, M. S. Historians and eighteenth-century Europe, 1715–1789 (Oxford UP, 1979); Jean de Viguerie, Histoire et dictionnaire du temps des Lumières (1715–1789) (Paris: Robert Laffont, 1995).
  161. ^ Frost, Martin (2008), The age of Enlightenment, archived from the original on 10 October 2007, retrieved 18 January 2008
  162. ^ Theodor W. Adorno; Horkheimer, Max (1947). «The Concept of Enlightenment». In G.S. Noerr (ed.). Dialectic of Enlightenment: Philosophical Fragments. Translated by E. Jephcott. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press. p. 3. ISBN 978-1-85984-154-9.
  163. ^ Josephson-Storm, Jason (2017). The Myth of Disenchantment: Magic, Modernity, and the Birth of the Human Sciences. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. pp. 58–61. ISBN 978-0-226-40336-6.
  164. ^ Josephson-Storm, Jason (2017). The Myth of Disenchantment: Magic, Modernity, and the Birth of the Human Sciences. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. pp. 61–62. ISBN 978-0-226-40336-6.
  165. ^ Outram, 6. See also, A. Owen Alridge (ed.), The Ibero-American Enlightenment (1971)., Franco Venturi, The End of the Old Regime in Europe 1768–1776: The First Crisis.
  166. ^ James Van Horn Melton, The Rise of the Public in Enlightenment Europe (2001), p. 4.
  167. ^ Jürgen Habermas, The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere, (1989), pp. 36, 37.
  168. ^ Melton, 8.
  169. ^ Nicolaas A. Rupke (2008). «Alexander Von Humboldt: A Metabiography«. University of Chicago Press. p. 138 ISBN 0-226-73149-9
  170. ^ Melton, 4, 5. Habermas, 14–26.
  171. ^ Daniel Brewer, ed. (2014). The Cambridge Companion to the French Enlightenment. Cambridge UP. pp. 91ff. ISBN 978-1-316-19432-4.
  172. ^ Outram, Dorinda. The Enlightenment (2nd ed.). Cambridge University Press, 2005, p. 12.
  173. ^ Outram 2005, p. 13.
  174. ^ Chartier, 27.
  175. ^ Mona Ozouf, «‘Public Opinion’ at the End of the Old Regime»
  176. ^ David Beard and Kenneth Gloag, Musicology, The Key Concepts (New York: Routledge, 2005), 58.
  177. ^ J. Peter Burkholder, Donald J. Grout, and Claude V. Palisca, A History of Western Music, Seventh Edition, (New York: W.W. Norton & Company, Inc., 2006), 475.
  178. ^ a b Beard and Gloag, Musicology, 59.
  179. ^ a b Beard and Gloag, Musicology, 60.
  180. ^ a b c Burkholder, Grout, and Palisca, A History of Western Music, 475.
  181. ^ a b c Outram, 21.
  182. ^ Chartier, 26.
  183. ^ Chartier, 26, 26. Kant, «What is Enlightenment?»
  184. ^ Outram, 23.
  185. ^ Goodman, 3.
  186. ^ Dena Goodman, The Republic of Letters: A Cultural History of the French Enlightenment (1994), 53.
  187. ^ Carla Hesse, The Other Enlightenment: How French Women Became Modern (2001), 42.
  188. ^ Crébillon fils, quoted from Darnton, The Literary Underground, 17.
  189. ^ Darnton, The Literary Underground, 19, 20.
  190. ^ Darnton, «The Literary Underground», 21, 23.
  191. ^ Darnton, The Literary Underground, 29
  192. ^ Outram, 22.
  193. ^ Darnton, The Literary Underground, 35–40.
  194. ^ Outram, 17, 20.
  195. ^ Darnton, «The Literary Underground», 16.
  196. ^ from Outram, 19. See Rolf Engelsing, «Die Perioden der Lesergeschichte in der Neuzeit. Das statische Ausmass und die soziokulturelle Bedeutung der Lektüre», Archiv für Geschichte des Buchwesens, 10 (1969), cols. 944–1002 and Der Bürger als Leser: Lesergeschichte in Deutschland, 1500–1800 (Stuttgart, 1974).
  197. ^ «history of publishing :: Developments in the 18th century». Encyclopædia Britannica.
  198. ^ Outram, 27–29
  199. ^ Erin Mackie, The Commerce of Everyday Life: Selections from The Tatler and The Spectator (Boston: Bedford/St. Martin’s, 1998), 16.
  200. ^ See Mackie, Darnton, An Early Information Society
  201. ^ In particular, see Chapter 6, «Reading, Writing and Publishing»
  202. ^ See Darnton, The Literary Underground, 184.
  203. ^ a b Darnton, The Literary Underground, 135–47.
  204. ^ Darnton, The Business of Enlightenment, 12, 13. For a more detailed description of French censorship laws, see Darnton, The Literary Underground
  205. ^ Eddy, Matthew Daniel (2008). The Language of Mineralogy: John Walker, Chemistry and the Edinburgh Medical School, 1750–1800. Ashgate.
  206. ^ Emma Spary, «The ‘Nature’ of Enlightenment» in The Sciences in Enlightened Europe, William Clark, Jan Golinski, and Steven Schaffer, eds. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1999), 281–82.
  207. ^ Spary, 289–93.
  208. ^ See Thomas Laqueur, Making sex: body and gender from the Greeks to Freud (1990).
  209. ^ Israel 2001, pp. 143–44.
  210. ^ Israel 2001, pp. 142.
  211. ^ Israel 2001, pp. 150–51.
  212. ^ a b Headrick, (2000), p. 144.
  213. ^ a b Headrick, (2000), p. 172.
  214. ^ Porter, (2003), pp. 249–250.
  215. ^ Headrick, (2000), p. 168.
  216. ^ Headrick, (2000), pp. 150–152.
  217. ^ Headrick, (2000), p. 153.
  218. ^ d’Alembert, p. 4.
  219. ^ Darnton, (1979), p. 7.
  220. ^ Darnton, (1979), p. 37.
  221. ^ Darnton, (1979), p. 6.
  222. ^ Jacob, (1988), p. 191; Melton, (2001), pp. 82–83
  223. ^ Headrick, (2000), p. 15
  224. ^ Headrick, (2000), p. 19.
  225. ^ Phillips, (1991), pp. 85, 90
  226. ^ Phillips, (1991), p. 90.
  227. ^ Porter, (2003), p. 300.
  228. ^ Porter, (2003), p. 101.
  229. ^ Phillips, (1991), p. 92.
  230. ^ Phillips, (1991), p. 107.
  231. ^ Eddy, Matthew Daniel (2013). «The Shape of Knowledge: Children and the Visual Culture of Literacy and Numeracy». Science in Context. 26 (2): 215–245. doi:10.1017/s0269889713000045. S2CID 147123263.
  232. ^ Hotson, Howard (2007). Commonplace Learning: Ramism and Its German Ramifications 1543–1630. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  233. ^ Eddy, Matthew Daniel (2008). The Language of Mineralogy: John Walker, Chemistry and the Edinburgh Medical School, 1750–1800. Aldershot: Ashgate.
  234. ^ Elizabeth Williams, A Cultural History of Medical Vitalism in Enlightenment Montpellier (2003) p. 50
  235. ^ Peter Barrett (2004), Science and Theology Since Copernicus: The Search for Understanding, p. 14, Continuum International Publishing Group, ISBN 0-567-08969-X
  236. ^ Daniel Roche, France in the Enlightenment, (1998), 420.
  237. ^ Roche, 515–16.
  238. ^ Caradonna JL. Annales, «Prendre part au siècle des Lumières: Le concours académique et la culture intellectuelle au XVIIIe siècle»
  239. ^ Jeremy L. Caradonna, «Prendre part au siècle des Lumières: Le concours académique et la culture intellectuelle au XVIIIe siècle», Annales. Histoire, Sciences sociales, vol. 64 (mai-juin 2009), n. 3, 633–62.
  240. ^ Caradonna, 634–36.
  241. ^ Caradonna, 653–54.
  242. ^ «Royal Charters». royalsociety.org.
  243. ^ Steven Shapin, A Social History of Truth: Civility and Science in Seventeenth-Century England, Chicago; London: University of Chicago Press, 1994.
  244. ^ Steven Shapin and Simon Schaffer, Leviathan and the Air-Pump: Hobbes, Boyle, and the Experimental Life (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1985), 5, 56, 57. This same desire for multiple witnesses led to attempts at replication in other locations and a complex iconography and literary technology developed to provide visual and written proof of experimentation. See pp. 59–65.
  245. ^ Shapin and Schaffer, 58, 59.
  246. ^ Klein, Lawrence E. (1 January 1996). «Coffeehouse Civility, 1660–1714: An Aspect of Post-Courtly Culture in England». Huntington Library Quarterly. 59 (1): 31–51. doi:10.2307/3817904. JSTOR 3817904.
  247. ^ Klein, 35.
  248. ^ Cowan, 90, 91.
  249. ^ Colin Jones, Paris: Biography of a City (New York: Viking, 2004), 188, 189.
  250. ^ Darnton, Robert (2000). «An Early Information Society: News and the Media in Eighteenth-Century Paris». The American Historical Review. 105#1 (1): 1–35. doi:10.2307/2652433. JSTOR 2652433.
  251. ^ Donna T. Andrew, «Popular Culture and Public Debate: London 1780», This Historical Journal, Vol. 39, No. 2. (June 1996), pp. 405–423.
  252. ^ Andrew, 406. Andrew gives the name as «William Henley», which must be a lapse of writing.
  253. ^ Andrew, 408.
  254. ^ Andrew, 406–08, 411.
  255. ^ a b Israel 2001, p. 4.
  256. ^ Andrew, 412–15.
  257. ^ Andrew, 422.
  258. ^ Crow, Matthew; Jacob, Margaret (2014). «Freemasonry and the Enlightenment». In Bodgan, Henrik; Snoek, Jan A. M. (eds.). Handbook of Freemasonry. Brill Handbooks on Contemporary Religion. Vol. 8. Leiden: Brill Publishers. pp. 100–116. doi:10.1163/9789004273122_008. ISBN 978-90-04-21833-8. ISSN 1874-6691.
  259. ^ Maynard Mack, Alexander Pope: A Life, Yale University Press, 1985 p. 437–440. Pope, a Catholic, was a Freemason in 1730, eight years before membership was prohibited by the Catholic Church (1738). Pope’s name is on the membership list of the Goat Tavern Lodge (p. 439). Pope’s name appears on a 1723 list and a 1730 list.
  260. ^ J.A. Leo Lemay (2013). The Life of Benjamin Franklin, Volume 2: Printer and Publisher, 1730–1747. University of Pennsylvania Press. pp. 83–92. ISBN 978-0-8122-0929-7.
  261. ^ Bullock, Steven C. (1996). «Initiating the Enlightenment?: Recent Scholarship on European Freemasonry». Eighteenth-Century Life. 20 (1): 81.
  262. ^ Norman Davies, Europe: A History (1996) pp. 634–635
  263. ^ Margaret C. Jacob’s seminal work on Enlightenment freemasonry, Margaret C. Jacob, Living the Enlightenment: Free masonry and Politics in Eighteenth-Century Europe (Oxford University Press, 1991) p. 49.
  264. ^ Margaret C. Jacob, «Polite worlds of Enlightenment,» in Martin Fitzpatrick and Peter Jones, eds. The Enlightenment World (Routledge, 2004) pp. 272–287.
  265. ^ Roche, 436.
  266. ^ Fitzpatrick and Jones, eds. The Enlightenment World p. 281
  267. ^ Jacob, pp. 20, 73, 89.
  268. ^ Jacob, 145–47.
  269. ^ Reinhart Koselleck, Critique and Crisis, p. 62, (The MIT Press, 1988)
  270. ^ Thomas Munck, 1994, p. 70.
  271. ^ Diderot, Denis (1769). «D’Alembert’s Dream» (PDF). Archived from the original (PDF) on 29 November 2014. Retrieved 17 November 2014.
  272. ^ Margaret C. Jacob, Living the Enlightenment: Freemasonry and politics in eighteenth-century Europe (Oxford University Press, 1991.)
  273. ^ Roche, 437.
  274. ^ Jacob, 139. See also Janet M. Burke, «Freemasonry, Friendship and Noblewomen: The Role of the Secret Society in Bringing Enlightenment Thought to Pre-Revolutionary Women Elites», History of European Ideas 10 no. 3 (1989): 283–94.
  275. ^ Davies, Europe: A History (1996) pp. 634–635
  276. ^ Richard Weisberger et al., eds., Freemasonry on both sides of the Atlantic: essays concerning the craft in the British Isles, Europe, the United States, and Mexico (2002)
  277. ^ Robert R. Palmer, The Age of the Democratic Revolution: The Struggle (1970) p. 53
  278. ^ Neil L. York, «Freemasons and the American Revolution», The Historian Volume: 55. Issue: 2. 1993, pp. 315+.
  279. ^ Janson, H. W.; Janson, Anthony (2003). A Basic History of Art. New York: Harry N. Abrams, Inc. pp. 458–474.

Sources[edit]

  • Andrew, Donna T. «Popular Culture and Public Debate: London 1780». The Historical Journal, Vol. 39, No. 2. (June 1996), pp. 405–423. in JSTOR
  • Burns, William. Science in the Enlightenment: An Encyclopædia (2003)
  • Cowan, Brian, The Social Life of Coffee: The Emergence of the British Coffeehouse. New Haven: Yale University Press, 2005
  • Darnton, Robert. The Literary Underground of the Old Regime. (1982).
  • Israel, Jonathan I. (2001). Radical Enlightenment; Philosophy and the Making of Modernity 1650–1750. Oxford University Press.
  • Israel, Jonathan I. (2006). Enlightenment Contested. Oxford University Press.
  • Israel, Jonathan I. (2010). A Revolution of the Mind: Radical Enlightenment and the Intellectual Origins of Modern Democracy. Princeton.
  • Israel, Jonathan I. (2011). Democratic Enlightenment: Philosophy, Revolution, and Human Rights 1750–1790. Oxford University Press.
  • Melton, James Van Horn. The Rise of the Public in Enlightenment Europe. (2001).
  • Petitfils, Jean-Christian (2005). Louis XVI. Perrin. ISBN 978-2-7441-9130-5.
  • Robertson, Ritchie. The Enlightenment: The Pursuit of Happiness, 1680–1790. London: Allen Lane, 2020; New York: HarperCollins, 2021
  • Ferrone, Vincenzo (2017). The Enlightenment: History of an Idea. Princeton University Press.
  • Pinker, Steven (2018). Enlightenment Now: The Case for Reason, Science, Humanism, and Progress. Penguin Books.
  • Roche, Daniel. France in the Enlightenment. (1998).

Further reading[edit]

Reference and surveys[edit]

  • Becker, Carl L. The Heavenly City of the Eighteenth-Century Philosophers. (1932), a famous short classic
  • Chisick, Harvey. Historical Dictionary of the Enlightenment (2005)
  • Delon, Michel. Encyclopædia of the Enlightenment (2001) 1480 pp.
  • Dupré, Louis. The Enlightenment and the Intellectual Foundations of Modern Culture (2004)
  • Gay, Peter. The Enlightenment: The Rise of Modern Paganism (1966, 2nd ed. 1995), 592 pp. excerpt and text search vol 1.
  • Gay, Peter. The Enlightenment: The Science of Freedom (1969, 2nd ed. 1995), a highly influential study excerpt and text search vol 2;
  • Greensides F., Hyland P., Gomez O. (ed.). The Enlightenment (2002)
  • Fitzpatrick, Martin et al., eds. The Enlightenment World (2004). 714 pp. 39 essays by scholars
  • Hampson, Norman. The Enlightenment (1981) online
  • Hazard, Paul. European Thought in the 18th Century: From Montesquieu to Lessing (1965)
  • Hesmyr, Atle. From Enlightenment to Romanticism in 18th Century Europe (2018)
  • Himmelfarb, Gertrude. The Roads to Modernity: The British, French, and American Enlightenments (2004) excerpt and text search
  • Jacob, Margaret. Enlightenment: A Brief History with Documents 2000
  • Kors, Alan Charles. Encyclopædia of the Enlightenment (4 vol. 1990; 2nd ed. 2003), 1984 pp. excerpt and text search
  • Lehner, Ulrich L. The Catholic Enlightenment (2016)
  • Lehner, Ulrich L. Women, Catholicism and Enlightenment (2017)
  • Munck, Thomas. Enlightenment: A Comparative Social History, 1721–1794 (1994)
  • Outram, Dorinda. The Enlightenment (1995) 157 pp. excerpt and text search; also online
  • Outram, Dorinda. Panorama of the Enlightenment (2006), emphasis on Germany; heavily illustrated
  • Porter, Roy (2001), The Enlightenment (2nd ed.), ISBN 978-0-333-94505-6
  • Reill, Peter Hanns, and Wilson, Ellen Judy. Encyclopædia of the Enlightenment. (2nd ed. 2004). 670 pp.
  • Robertson, Ritchie. The Enlightenment: The Pursuit of Happiness, 1680-1790. (2021).
  • Sarmant, Thierry (2012). Histoire de Paris: Politique, urbanisme, civilisation. Editions Jean-Paul Gisserot. ISBN 978-2-7558-0330-3.
  • Warman, Caroline; et al. (2016), Warman, Caroline (ed.), Tolerance: The Beacon of the Enlightenment, Open Book Publishers, doi:10.11647/OBP.0088, ISBN 978-1-78374-203-5
  • Yolton, John W. et al. The Blackwell Companion to the Enlightenment. (1992). 581 pp.

Specialty studies[edit]

  • Aldridge, A. Owen (ed.). The Ibero-American Enlightenment (1971).
  • Artz, Frederick B. The Enlightenment in France (1998) online
  • Brewer, Daniel. The Enlightenment Past: Reconstructing 18th-Century French Thought (2008)
  • Broadie, Alexander. The Scottish Enlightenment: The Historical Age of the Historical Nation (2007)
  • Broadie, Alexander. The Cambridge Companion to the Scottish Enlightenment (2003) excerpt and text search
  • Bronner, Stephen (1995). «The Great Divide: The Enlightenment and its Critics». New Politics. 5: 65–86.
  • Brown, Stuart, ed. British Philosophy in the Age of Enlightenment (2002)
  • Buchan, James. Crowded with Genius: The Scottish Enlightenment: Edinburgh’s Moment of the Mind (2004) excerpt and text search
  • Burrows, Simon. (2013) «In Search of Enlightenment: From Mapping Books to Cultural History.» Journal for Early Modern Cultural Studies 13, no. 4: 3–28.
  • Campbell, R.S. and Skinner, A.S., (eds.) The Origins and Nature of the Scottish Enlightenment, Edinburgh, 1982
  • Cassirer, Ernst. The Philosophy of the Enlightenment. 1955. a highly influential study by a neoKantian philosopher excerpt and text search
  • Chartier, Roger. The Cultural Origins of the French Revolution. Translated by Lydia G. Cochrane. Duke University Press, 1991.
  • Europe in the age of enlightenment and revolution. New York: The Metropolitan Museum of Art. 1989. ISBN 978-0-87099-451-7.
  • Edelstein, Dan. The Enlightenment: A Genealogy (University of Chicago Press; 2010) 209 pp.
  • Golinski, Jan (2011). «Science in the Enlightenment, Revisited». History of Science. 49 (2): 217–231. Bibcode:2011HisSc..49..217G. doi:10.1177/007327531104900204. S2CID 142886527.
  • Goodman, Dena. The Republic of Letters: A Cultural History of the French Enlightenment. (1994).
  • Hesse, Carla. The Other Enlightenment: How French Women Became Modern. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2001.
  • Hankins, Thomas L. Science and the Enlightenment (1985).
  • May, Henry F. The Enlightenment in America. 1976. 419 pp.
  • Porter, Roy. The Creation of the Modern World: The Untold Story of the British Enlightenment. 2000. 608 pp. excerpt and text search
  • Redkop, Benjamin. The Enlightenment and Community, 1999
  • Reid-Maroney, Nina. Philadelphia’s Enlightenment, 1740–1800: Kingdom of Christ, Empire of Reason. 2001. 199 pp.
  • Schmidt, James (2003). «Inventing the Enlightenment: Anti-Jacobins, British Hegelians, and the ‘Oxford English Dictionary’«. Journal of the History of Ideas. 64 (3): 421–443. doi:10.2307/3654234. JSTOR 3654234.
  • Sorkin, David. The Religious Enlightenment: Protestants, Jews, and Catholics from London to Vienna (2008)
  • Staloff, Darren. Hamilton, Adams, Jefferson: The Politics of Enlightenment and the American Founding. 2005. 419 pp. excerpt and text search
  • Suitner, Riccarda. The Dialogues of the Dead of the Early German Enlightenment (Leiden-Boston: Brill, 2022)
  • Till, Nicholas. Mozart and the Enlightenment: Truth, Virtue, and Beauty in Mozart’s Operas. 1993. 384 pp.
  • Tunstall, Kate E. Blindness and Enlightenment. An Essay. With a new translation of Diderot’s Letter on the Blind (Continuum, 2011)
  • Venturi, Franco. Utopia and Reform in the Enlightenment. George Macaulay Trevelyan Lecture, (1971)
  • Venturi, Franco. Italy and the Enlightenment: studies in a cosmopolitan century (1972) online
  • Wills, Garry. Cincinnatus: George Washington and the Enlightenment (1984) online
  • Winterer, Caroline. American Enlightenments: Pursuing Happiness in the Age of Reason (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2016)
  • Navarro i Soriano, Ferran (2019). Harca, harca, harca! Músiques per a la recreació històrica de la Guerra de Successió (1794–1715). Editorial DENES. ISBN 978-84-16473-45-8.

Primary sources[edit]

  • Broadie, Alexander, ed. The Scottish Enlightenment: An Anthology (2001) excerpt and text search
  • Diderot, Denis. Rameau’s Nephew and other Works (2008) excerpt and text search.
  • Diderot, Denis. «Letter on the Blind» in Tunstall, Kate E. Blindness and Enlightenment. An Essay. With a new translation of Diderot’s Letter on the Blind (Continuum, 2011)
  • Diderot, Denis. The Encyclopédie of Diderot and D’Alembert: Selected Articles (1969) excerpt and text search Collaborative Translation Project of the University of Michigan
  • Gay, Peter, ed. (1973). The Enlightenment: A Comprehensive Anthology. ISBN 0671217070.
  • Gomez, Olga, et al. eds. The Enlightenment: A Sourcebook and Reader (2001) excerpt and text search
  • Kramnick, Issac, ed. The Portable Enlightenment Reader (1995) excerpt and text search
  • Manuel, Frank Edward, ed. The Enlightenment (1965) online, excerpts
  • Schmidt, James, ed. What is Enlightenment?: Eighteenth-Century Answers and Twentieth-Century Questions (1996) excerpt and text search

External links[edit]

  • Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). «Enlightenment». Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Age of Enlightenment at PhilPapers
  • Age of Enlightenment at the Indiana Philosophy Ontology Project
  • Collection: Art of the Enlightenment Era from the University of Michigan Museum of Art

The Age of Enlightenment or the Enlightenment[note 2] was an intellectual and philosophical movement that dominated Europe in the 17th and 18th centuries with global influences and effects.[2][3] The Enlightenment included a range of ideas centered on the value of human happiness, the pursuit of knowledge obtained by means of reason and the evidence of the senses, and ideals such as natural law, liberty, progress, toleration, fraternity, constitutional government, and separation of church and state.[4][5]

The Enlightenment was preceded by the Scientific Revolution and the work of Francis Bacon, John Locke, among others. Some date the beginning of the Enlightenment to the publication of René Descartes’ Discourse on the Method in 1637, featuring his famous dictum, Cogito, ergo sum («I think, therefore I am»). Others cite the publication of Isaac Newton’s Principia Mathematica (1687) as the culmination of the Scientific Revolution and the beginning of the Enlightenment. European historians traditionally date in the past four decades and is a chemical symbol for a new pair of shoes its beginning with the death of Louis XIV of France in 1715 and its end with the 1789 outbreak of the French Revolution. Many historians now date the end of the Enlightenment as the start of the 19th century, with the latest proposed year being the death of Immanuel Kant in 1804.

Philosophers and scientists of the period widely circulated their ideas through meetings at scientific academies, Masonic lodges, literary salons, coffeehouses and in printed books, journals,[6] and pamphlets. The ideas of the Enlightenment undermined the authority of the monarchy and the Catholic Church and paved the way for the political revolutions of the 18th and 19th centuries. A variety of 19th century movements including liberalism, communism, and neoclassicism trace their intellectual heritage to the Enlightenment.[7]

The central doctrines of the Enlightenment were individual liberty and religious tolerance, in opposition to an absolute monarchy and the fixed dogmas of the Church. The concepts of utility and sociability were also crucial in the dissemination of information that would better society as a whole. The Enlightenment was marked by an increasing awareness of the relationship between the mind and the everyday media of the world,[8] and by an emphasis on the scientific method and reductionism, along with increased questioning of religious orthodoxy—an attitude captured by Kant’s essay Answering the Question: What is Enlightenment, where the phrase Sapere aude (Dare to know) can be found.[9]

Important intellectuals[edit]

The most famous work by Nicholas de Condorcet, Esquisse d’un tableau historique des progres de l’esprit humain, 1795.[10] With the publication of this book, the development of the Age of Enlightenment is considered generally ended.[11]

The Age of Enlightenment was preceded by and closely associated with the Scientific Revolution.[12] Earlier philosophers whose work influenced the Enlightenment included Francis Bacon and René Descartes.[13] Some of the major figures of the Enlightenment included Cesare Beccaria, Denis Diderot, David Hume, Immanuel Kant, Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, John Locke, Montesquieu, Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Adam Smith, Hugo Grotius, Baruch Spinoza, and Voltaire.[14]

One particularly influential Enlightenment publication was the Encyclopédie (Encyclopedia). Published between 1751 and 1772 in 35 volumes, it was compiled by Diderot, Jean le Rond d’Alembert, and a team of 150 other intellectuals. The Encyclopédie helped in spreading the ideas of the Enlightenment across Europe and beyond.[15] Other landmark publications of the Enlightenment included Voltaire’s Letters on the English (1733) and Dictionnaire philosophique (Philosophical Dictionary; 1764); Hume’s A Treatise of Human Nature (1740); Montesquieu’s The Spirit of the Laws (1748); Rousseau’s Discourse on Inequality (1754) and The Social Contract (1762); Adam Smith’s The Theory of Moral Sentiments (1759) and The Wealth of Nations (1776); and Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason (1781).

Topics[edit]

Philosophy[edit]

Bacon’s empiricism and Descartes’ rationalist philosophy laid the foundation for enlightenment thinking.[16] Descartes’ attempt to construct the sciences on a secure metaphysical foundation was not as successful as his method of doubt applied in philosophic areas leading to a dualistic doctrine of mind and matter. His skepticism was refined by Locke’s Essay Concerning Human Understanding (1690) and Hume’s writings in the 1740s. His dualism was challenged by Spinoza’s uncompromising assertion of the unity of matter in his Tractatus (1670) and Ethics (1677).

According to Jonathan Israel, these laid down two distinct lines of Enlightenment thought: first, the moderate variety, following Descartes, Locke, and Christian Wolff, which sought accommodation between reform and the traditional systems of power and faith, and, second, the Radical Enlightenment, inspired by the philosophy of Spinoza, advocating democracy, individual liberty, freedom of expression, and eradication of religious authority.[17][18] The moderate variety tended to be deistic whereas the radical tendency separated the basis of morality entirely from theology. Both lines of thought were eventually opposed by a conservative Counter-Enlightenment which sought a return to faith.[19]

In the mid-18th century, Paris became the center of philosophic and scientific activity challenging traditional doctrines and dogmas. The philosophical movement was led by Voltaire and Rousseau, who argued for a society based upon reason as in ancient Greece[20] rather than faith and Catholic doctrine, for a new civil order based on natural law, and for science based on experiments and observation. The political philosopher Montesquieu introduced the idea of a separation of powers in a government, a concept which was enthusiastically adopted by the authors of the United States Constitution. While the philosophes of the French Enlightenment were not revolutionaries and many were members of the nobility, their ideas played an important part in undermining the legitimacy of the Old Regime and shaping the French Revolution.[21]

Francis Hutcheson, a moral philosopher and founding figure of the Scottish Enlightenment, described the utilitarian and consequentialist principle that virtue is that which provides, in his words, «the greatest happiness for the greatest numbers». Much of what is incorporated in the scientific method (the nature of knowledge, evidence, experience, and causation) and some modern attitudes towards the relationship between science and religion were developed by Hutcheson’s protégés in Edinburgh: David Hume and Adam Smith.[22][23] Hume became a major figure in the skeptical philosophical and empiricist traditions of philosophy.

Kant tried to reconcile rationalism and religious belief, individual freedom and political authority, as well as map out a view of the public sphere through private and public reason.[24] Kant’s work continued to shape German thought and indeed all of European philosophy, well into the 20th century.[25]

Mary Wollstonecraft was one of England’s earliest feminist philosophers.[26] She argued for a society based on reason and that women as well as men should be treated as rational beings. She is best known for her work A Vindication of the Rights of Woman (1791).[27]

Science[edit]

Science played an important role in Enlightenment discourse and thought. Many Enlightenment writers and thinkers had backgrounds in the sciences and associated scientific advancement with the overthrow of religion and traditional authority in favour of the development of free speech and thought. Scientific progress during the Enlightenment included the discovery of carbon dioxide (fixed air) by chemist Joseph Black, the argument for deep time by geologist James Hutton, and the invention of the condensing steam engine by James Watt.[28] The experiments of Antoine Lavoisier were used to create the first modern chemical plants in Paris, and the experiments of the Montgolfier brothers enabled them to launch the first manned flight in a hot air balloon in 1783.[29] The wide-ranging contributions to mathematics of Leonhard Euler included major results in analysis, number theory, topology, combinatorics, graph theory, algebra, and geometry (among other fields). In applied mathematics, he made fundamental contributions to mechanics, hydraulics, acoustics, optics, and astronomy.

Broadly speaking, Enlightenment science greatly valued empiricism and rational thought and was embedded with the Enlightenment ideal of advancement and progress. The study of science, under the heading of natural philosophy, was divided into physics and a conglomerate grouping of chemistry and natural history, which included anatomy, biology, geology, mineralogy, and zoology.[30] As with most Enlightenment views, the benefits of science were not seen universally: Rousseau criticized the sciences for distancing man from nature and not operating to make people happier.[31]

Science during the Enlightenment was dominated by scientific societies and academies, which had largely replaced universities as centres of scientific research and development. Societies and academies were also the backbone of the maturation of the scientific profession. Scientific academies and societies grew out of the Scientific Revolution as the creators of scientific knowledge, in contrast to the scholasticism of the university.[32] Some societies created or retained links to universities, but contemporary sources distinguished universities from scientific societies by claiming that the university’s utility was in the transmission of knowledge while societies functioned to create knowledge.[33] As the role of universities in institutionalized science began to diminish, learned societies became the cornerstone of organized science. Official scientific societies were chartered by the state to provide technical expertise.[34]

Most societies were granted permission to oversee their own publications, control the election of new members and the administration of the society.[35] In the 18th century, a tremendous number of official academies and societies were founded in Europe, and by 1789 there were over 70 official scientific societies. In reference to this growth, Bernard de Fontenelle coined the term «the Age of Academies» to describe the 18th century.[36]

Another important development was the popularization of science among an increasingly literate population. Philosophes introduced the public to many scientific theories, most notably through the Encyclopédie and the popularization of Newtonianism by Voltaire and Émilie du Châtelet. Some historians have marked the 18th century as a drab period in the history of science.[37] The century saw significant advancements in the practice of medicine, mathematics, and physics; the development of biological taxonomy; a new understanding of magnetism and electricity; and the maturation of chemistry as a discipline, which established the foundations of modern chemistry.

The influence of science began appearing more commonly in poetry and literature. Some poetry became infused with scientific metaphor and imagery, while other poems were written directly about scientific topics. Richard Blackmore committed the Newtonian system to verse in Creation, a Philosophical Poem in Seven Books (1712). After Newton’s death in 1727, poems were composed in his honour for decades.[38] James Thomson penned his «Poem to the Memory of Newton», which mourned the loss of Newton and praised his science and legacy.[39]

Sociology, economics, and law[edit]

Hume and other Scottish Enlightenment thinkers developed a «science of man»,[40] which was expressed historically in works by authors including James Burnett, Adam Ferguson, John Millar, and William Robertson, all of whom merged a scientific study of how humans behaved in ancient and primitive cultures with a strong awareness of the determining forces of modernity. Modern sociology largely originated from this movement,[41] and Hume’s philosophical concepts that directly influenced James Madison (and thus the U.S. Constitution), and as popularised by Dugald Stewart was the basis of classical liberalism.[42]

In 1776, Adam Smith published The Wealth of Nations, often considered the first work on modern economics as it had an immediate impact on British economic policy that continues into the 21st century.[43] It was immediately preceded and influenced by Anne Robert Jacques Turgot’s drafts of Reflections on the Formation and Distribution of Wealth (1766). Smith acknowledged indebtedness and possibly was the original English translator.[44]

Beccaria, a jurist, criminologist, philosopher, and politician and one of the great Enlightenment writers, became famous for his masterpiece Of Crimes and Punishments (1764), later translated into 22 languages,[45] which condemned torture and the death penalty and was a founding work in the field of penology and the classical school of criminology by promoting criminal justice. Francesco Mario Pagano wrote important studies such as Saggi politici (Political Essays, 1783); and Considerazioni sul processo criminale (Considerations on the Criminal Trial, 1787), which established him as an international authority on criminal law.[46]

Politics[edit]

The Enlightenment has long been seen as the foundation of modern Western political and intellectual culture.[47] The Enlightenment brought political modernization to the West, in terms of introducing democratic values and institutions and the creation of modern, liberal democracies. This thesis has been widely accepted by scholars and has been reinforced by the large-scale studies by Robert Darnton, Roy Porter, and, most recently, by Jonathan Israel.[48][49] Enlightenment thought was deeply influential in the political realm. European rulers such as Catherine II of Russia, Joseph II of Austria, and Frederick II of Prussia tried to apply Enlightenment thought on religious and political tolerance, which became known as enlightened absolutism.[14] Many of the major political and intellectual figures behind the American Revolution associated themselves closely with the Enlightenment: Benjamin Franklin visited Europe repeatedly and contributed actively to the scientific and political debates there and brought the newest ideas back to Philadelphia; Thomas Jefferson closely followed European ideas and later incorporated some of the ideals of the Enlightenment into the Declaration of Independence; and Madison incorporated these ideals into the U.S. Constitution during its framing in 1787.[50]

Theories of government[edit]

Locke, one of the most influential Enlightenment thinkers,[51] based his governance philosophy in social contract theory, a subject that permeated Enlightenment political thought. English philosopher Thomas Hobbes ushered in this new debate with his work Leviathan in 1651. Hobbes also developed some of the fundamentals of European liberal thought: the right of the individual, the natural equality of all men, the artificial character of the political order (which led to the later distinction between civil society and the state), the view that all legitimate political power must be «representative» and based on the consent of the people, and a liberal interpretation of law which leaves people free to do whatever the law does not explicitly forbid.[52]

Both Locke and Rousseau developed social contract theories in Two Treatises of Government and Discourse on Inequality, respectively. While quite different works, Locke, Hobbes, and Rousseau agreed that a social contract, in which the government’s authority lies in the consent of the governed,[53] is necessary for man to live in civil society. Locke defines the state of nature as a condition in which humans are rational and follow natural law, in which all men are born equal and with the right to life, liberty, and property. However, when one citizen breaks the law of nature both the transgressor and the victim enter into a state of war, from which it is virtually impossible to break free. Therefore, Locke said that individuals enter into civil society to protect their natural rights via an «unbiased judge» or common authority, such as courts. In contrast, Rousseau’s conception relies on the supposition that «civil man» is corrupted, while «natural man» has no want he cannot fulfill himself. Natural man is only taken out of the state of nature when the inequality associated with private property is established.[54] Rousseau said that people join into civil society via the social contract to achieve unity while preserving individual freedom. This is embodied in the sovereignty of the general will, the moral and collective legislative body constituted by citizens.

Locke is known for his statement that individuals have a right to «Life, Liberty, and Property,» and his belief that the natural right to property is derived from labor. Tutored by Locke, Anthony Ashley-Cooper, 3rd Earl of Shaftesbury, wrote in 1706: «There is a mighty Light which spreads its self over the world especially in those two free Nations of England and Holland; on whom the Affairs of Europe now turn.»[55] Locke’s theory of natural rights has influenced many political documents, including the U.S. Declaration of Independence and the French National Constituent Assembly’s Declaration of the Rights of Man and of the Citizen.

The philosophes argued that the establishment of a contractual basis of rights would lead to the market mechanism and capitalism, the scientific method, religious tolerance, and the organization of states into self-governing republics through democratic means. In this view, the tendency of the philosophes in particular to apply rationality to every problem is considered the essential change.[56]

Although much of Enlightenment political thought was dominated by social contract theorists, Hume and Ferguson criticized this camp. Hume’s essay Of the Original Contract argues that governments derived from consent are rarely seen and civil government is grounded in a ruler’s habitual authority and force. It is precisely because of the ruler’s authority over-and-against the subject that the subject tacitly consents, and Hume says that the subjects would «never imagine that their consent made him sovereign», rather the authority did so.[57] Similarly, Ferguson did not believe citizens built the state, rather polities grew out of social development. In his 1767 An Essay on the History of Civil Society, Ferguson uses the four stages of progress, a theory that was popular in Scotland at the time, to explain how humans advance from a hunting and gathering society to a commercial and civil society without agreeing to a social contract.

Both Rousseau’s and Locke’s social contract theories rest on the presupposition of natural rights, which are not a result of law or custom but are things that all men have in pre-political societies and are therefore universal and inalienable. The most famous natural right formulation comes from Locke’s Second Treatise, when he introduces the state of nature. For Locke, the law of nature is grounded on mutual security or the idea that one cannot infringe on another’s natural rights, as every man is equal and has the same inalienable rights. These natural rights include perfect equality and freedom, as well as the right to preserve life and property.

Locke argues against indentured servitude on the basis that enslaving oneself goes against the law of nature because a person cannot surrender their own rights: freedom is absolute, and no one can take it away. Locke argues that one person cannot enslave another because it is morally reprehensible, although he introduces a caveat by saying that enslavement of a lawful captive in time of war would not go against one’s natural rights. As a spill-over of the Enlightenment, nonsecular beliefs expressed first by Quakers and then by Protestant evangelicals in Britain and the United States emerged. To these groups, slavery became «repugnant to our religion» and a «crime in the sight of God».[58] These ideas added to those expressed by Enlightenment thinkers, leading many in Britain to believe that slavery was «not only morally wrong and economically inefficient, but also politically unwise.» This ideals eventually led to the abolition of slavery in Britain and the United States.[59]

Enlightened absolutism[edit]

The Marquis of Pombal, as the head of the government of Portugal, implemented sweeping socio-economic reforms

The leaders of the Enlightenment were not especially democratic, as they more often look to absolute monarchs as the key to imposing reforms designed by the intellectuals. Voltaire despised democracy and said the absolute monarch must be enlightened and must act as dictated by reason and justice—in other words, be a «philosopher-king».[60]

Denmark’s minister Johann Struensee, a social reformer, was publicly executed in 1772 for usurping royal authority

In several nations, rulers welcomed leaders of the Enlightenment at court and asked them to help design laws and programs to reform the system, typically to build stronger states. These rulers are called «enlightened despots» by historians.[61] They included Frederick the Great of Prussia, Catherine the Great of Russia, Leopold II of Tuscany and Joseph II of Austria. Joseph was over-enthusiastic, announcing many reforms that had little support so that revolts broke out and his regime became a comedy of errors, and nearly all his programs were reversed.[62] Senior ministers Pombal in Portugal and Johann Friedrich Struensee in Denmark also governed according to Enlightenment ideals. In Poland, the model constitution of 1791 expressed Enlightenment ideals, but was in effect for only one year before the nation was partitioned among its neighbors. More enduring were the cultural achievements, which created a nationalist spirit in Poland.[63]

Frederick the Great, the king of Prussia from 1740 to 1786, saw himself as a leader of the Enlightenment and patronized philosophers and scientists at his court in Berlin. Voltaire, who had been imprisoned and maltreated by the French government, was eager to accept Frederick’s invitation to live at his palace. Frederick explained: «My principal occupation is to combat ignorance and prejudice… to enlighten minds, cultivate morality, and to make people as happy as it suits human nature, and as the means at my disposal permit.»[64]

American Revolution and French Revolution[edit]

The Enlightenment has been frequently linked to the American Revolution of 1776[65] and the French Revolution of 1789—both had some intellectual influence from Thomas Jefferson.[66][67] One view of the political changes that occurred during the Enlightenment is that the «consent of the governed» philosophy as delineated by Locke in Two Treatises of Government (1689) represented a paradigm shift from the old governance paradigm under feudalism known as the «divine right of kings». In this view, the revolutions were caused by the fact that this governance paradigm shift often could not be resolved peacefully and therefore violent revolution was the result. A governance philosophy where the king was never wrong would be in direct conflict with one whereby citizens by natural law had to consent to the acts and rulings of their government.

Alexis de Tocqueville proposed the French Revolution as the inevitable result of the radical opposition created in the 18th century between the monarchy and the men of letters of the Enlightenment. These men of letters constituted a sort of «substitute aristocracy that was both all-powerful and without real power.» This illusory power came from the rise of «public opinion», born when absolutist centralization removed the nobility and the bourgeoisie from the political sphere. The «literary politics» that resulted promoted a discourse of equality and was hence in fundamental opposition to the monarchical regime.[68] De Tocqueville «clearly designates… the cultural effects of transformation in the forms of the exercise of power.»[69]

Religion[edit]

It does not require great art or magnificently trained eloquence, to prove that Christians should tolerate each other. I, however, am going further: I say that we should regard all men as our brothers. What? The Turk my brother? The Chinaman my brother? The Jew? The Siam? Yes, without doubt; are we not all children of the same father and creatures of the same God?

Voltaire (1763)[70]

Enlightenment era religious commentary was a response to the preceding century of religious conflict in Europe, especially the Thirty Years’ War.[71] Theologians of the Enlightenment wanted to reform their faith to its generally non-confrontational roots and to limit the capacity for religious controversy to spill over into politics and warfare while still maintaining a true faith in God. For moderate Christians, this meant a return to simple Scripture. Locke abandoned the corpus of theological commentary in favor of an «unprejudiced examination» of the Word of God alone. He determined the essence of Christianity to be a belief in Christ the redeemer and recommended avoiding more detailed debate.[72] Anthony Collins, one of the English freethinkers, published his «Essay concerning the Use of Reason in Propositions the Evidence whereof depends on Human Testimony» (1707), in which he rejects the distinction between «above reason» and «contrary to reason», and demands that revelation should conform to man’s natural ideas of God. In the Jefferson Bible, Thomas Jefferson (who adhered to Epicurean philosophy) went further and dropped any passages dealing with miracles, visitations of angels, and the resurrection of Jesus after his death, as he tried to extract the practical Christian moral code of the New Testament.[73]

Enlightenment scholars sought to curtail the political power of organized religion and thereby prevent another age of intolerant religious war.[74] Spinoza determined to remove politics from contemporary and historical theology (e.g., disregarding Judaic law).[75] Moses Mendelssohn advised affording no political weight to any organized religion but instead recommended that each person follow what they found most convincing.[76] They believed a good religion based in instinctive morals and a belief in God should not theoretically need force to maintain order in its believers, and both Mendelssohn and Spinoza judged religion on its moral fruits, not the logic of its theology.[77]

Several novel ideas about religion developed with the Enlightenment, including deism and talk of atheism. According to Thomas Paine, deism is the simple belief in God the Creator with no reference to the Bible or any other miraculous source. Instead, the deist relies solely on personal reason to guide his creed,[78] which was eminently agreeable to many thinkers of the time.[79] Atheism was much discussed, but there were few proponents. Wilson and Reill note: «In fact, very few enlightened intellectuals, even when they were vocal critics of Christianity, were true atheists. Rather, they were critics of orthodox belief, wedded rather to skepticism, deism, vitalism, or perhaps pantheism.»[80] Some followed Pierre Bayle and argued that atheists could indeed be moral men.[81] Many others like Voltaire held that without belief in a God who punishes evil, the moral order of society was undermined; that is, since atheists gave themselves to no supreme authority and no law and had no fear of eternal consequences, they were far more likely to disrupt society.[82] Bayle observed that, in his day, «prudent persons will always maintain an appearance of [religion],» and he believed that even atheists could hold concepts of honor and go beyond their own self-interest to create and interact in society.[83] Locke said that if there were no God and no divine law, the result would be moral anarchy: every individual «could have no law but his own will, no end but himself. He would be a god to himself, and the satisfaction of his own will the sole measure and end of all his actions.»[84]

Separation of church and state[edit]

The «Radical Enlightenment»[85][86] promoted the concept of separating church and state,[87] an idea that is often credited to Locke.[88] According to his principle of the social contract, Locke said that the government lacked authority in the realm of individual conscience, as this was something rational people could not cede to the government for it or others to control. For Locke, this created a natural right in the liberty of conscience, which he said must therefore remain protected from any government authority.

These views on religious tolerance and the importance of individual conscience, along with the social contract, became particularly influential in the American colonies and the drafting of the United States Constitution.[89] In a letter to the Danbury Baptist Association in Connecticut, Thomas Jefferson calls for a «wall of separation between church and state» at the federal level. He previously had supported successful efforts to disestablish the Church of England in Virginia[90] and authored the Virginia Statute for Religious Freedom.[91] Jefferson’s political ideals were greatly influenced by the writings of Locke, Bacon, and Newton,[92] whom he considered the three greatest men that ever lived.[93]

National variations[edit]

The Enlightenment took hold in most European countries and influenced nations globally, often with a specific local emphasis. For example, in France it became associated with anti-government and anti-Church radicalism, while in Germany it reached deep into the middle classes, where it expressed a spiritualistic and nationalistic tone without threatening governments or established churches.[94] Government responses varied widely. In France, the government was hostile, and the philosophes fought against its censorship, sometimes being imprisoned or hounded into exile. The British government, for the most part, ignored the Enlightenment’s leaders in England and Scotland, although it did give Newton a knighthood and a very lucrative government office.[6]

A common theme among most countries which derived Enlightenment ideas from Europe was the intentional non-inclusion of Enlightenment philosophies pertaining to slavery. Originally during the French Revolution, a revolution deeply inspired by Enlightenment philosophy, «France’s revolutionary government had denounced slavery, but the property-holding ‘revolutionaries’ then remembered their bank accounts.»[95] Slavery frequently showed the limitations of the Enlightenment ideology as it pertained to European colonialism, since many colonies of Europe operated on a plantation economy fueled by slave labor. In 1791, the Haitian Revolution, a slave rebellion by emancipated slaves against French colonial rule in the colony of Saint-Domingue, broke out. European nations and the United States, despite the strong support for Enlightenment ideals, refused to «[give support] to Saint-Domingue’s anti-colonial struggle.»[95]

Great Britain[edit]

England[edit]

The very existence of an English Enlightenment has been hotly debated by scholars. The majority of textbooks on British history make little or no mention of an English Enlightenment. Some surveys of the entire Enlightenment include England and others ignore it, although they do include coverage of such major intellectuals as Joseph Addison, Edward Gibbon, John Locke, Isaac Newton, Alexander Pope, Joshua Reynolds, and Jonathan Swift.[96] Freethinking, a term describing those who stood in opposition to the institution of the Church, and the literal belief in the Bible, can be said to have begun in England no later than 1713, when Anthony Collins wrote his «Discourse of Free-thinking», which gained substantial popularity. This essay attacked the clergy of all churches and was a plea for deism.

Roy Porter argues that the reasons for this neglect were the assumptions that the movement was primarily French-inspired, that it was largely a-religious or anti-clerical, and that it stood in outspoken defiance to the established order.[97] Porter admits that after the 1720s England could claim thinkers to equal Diderot, Voltaire, or Rousseau. However, its leading intellectuals such as Gibbon,[98] Edmund Burke and Samuel Johnson were all quite conservative and supportive of the standing order. Porter says the reason was that Enlightenment had come early to England and had succeeded such that the culture had accepted political liberalism, philosophical empiricism, and religious toleration, positions which intellectuals on the continent had to fight against powerful odds. Furthermore, England rejected the collectivism of the continent and emphasized the improvement of individuals as the main goal of enlightenment.[99]

One leader of the Scottish Enlightenment was Adam Smith, the father of modern economic science

Scotland[edit]

In the Scottish Enlightenment, the principles of sociability, equality, and utility were disseminated in schools and universities, many of which used sophisticated teaching methods which blended philosophy with daily life.[100] Scotland’s major cities created an intellectual infrastructure of mutually supporting institutions such as schools, universities, reading societies, libraries, periodicals, museums, and masonic lodges.[101] The Scottish network was «predominantly liberal Calvinist, Newtonian, and ‘design’ oriented in character which played a major role in the further development of the transatlantic Enlightenment».[102] In France, Voltaire said «we look to Scotland for all our ideas of civilization».[103] The focus of the Scottish Enlightenment ranged from intellectual and economic matters to the specifically scientific as in the work of William Cullen, physician and chemist; James Anderson, agronomist; Joseph Black, physicist and chemist; and James Hutton, the first modern geologist.[22][104]

Anglo-American colonies[edit]

Several Americans, especially Benjamin Franklin and Thomas Jefferson, played a major role in bringing Enlightenment ideas to the New World and in influencing British and French thinkers.[105] Franklin was influential for his political activism and for his advances in physics.[106][107] The cultural exchange during the Age of Enlightenment ran in both directions across the Atlantic. Thinkers such as Paine, Locke, and Rousseau all take Native American cultural practices as examples of natural freedom.[108] The Americans closely followed English and Scottish political ideas, as well as some French thinkers such as Montesquieu.[109] As deists, they were influenced by ideas of John Toland and Matthew Tindal. There was a great emphasis upon liberty, republicanism, and religious tolerance. There was no respect for monarchy or inherited political power. Deists reconciled science and religion by rejecting prophecies, miracles, and biblical theology. Leading deists included Thomas Paine in The Age of Reason and Thomas Jefferson in his short Jefferson Bible, from which he removed all supernatural aspects.[110]

German states[edit]

Prussia took the lead among the German states in sponsoring the political reforms that Enlightenment thinkers urged absolute rulers to adopt. There were important movements as well in the smaller states of Bavaria, Saxony, Hanover, and the Palatinate. In each case, Enlightenment values became accepted and led to significant political and administrative reforms that laid the groundwork for the creation of modern states.[111] The princes of Saxony, for example, carried out an impressive series of fundamental fiscal, administrative, judicial, educational, cultural, and general economic reforms. The reforms were aided by the country’s strong urban structure and influential commercial groups and modernized pre-1789 Saxony along the lines of classic Enlightenment principles.[112][113]

Before 1750, the German upper classes looked to France for intellectual, cultural, and architectural leadership, as French was the language of high society. By the mid-18th century, the Aufklärung (The Enlightenment) had transformed German high culture in music, philosophy, science, and literature. Christian Wolff was the pioneer as a writer who expounded the Enlightenment to German readers and legitimized German as a philosophic language.[114]

Johann Gottfried von Herder broke new ground in philosophy and poetry, as a leader of the Sturm und Drang movement of proto-Romanticism. Weimar Classicism (Weimarer Klassik) was a cultural and literary movement based in Weimar that sought to establish a new humanism by synthesizing Romantic, classical, and Enlightenment ideas. The movement (from 1772 until 1805) involved Herder as well as polymath Johann Wolfgang von Goethe and Friedrich Schiller, a poet and historian. Herder argued that every group of people had its own particular identity, which was expressed in its language and culture. This legitimized the promotion of German language and culture and helped shape the development of German nationalism. Schiller’s plays expressed the restless spirit of his generation, depicting the hero’s struggle against social pressures and the force of destiny.[115]

German music, sponsored by the upper classes, came of age under composers Johann Sebastian Bach, Joseph Haydn, and Wolfgang Amadeus Mozart.[116]

In remote Königsberg, Kant tried to reconcile rationalism and religious belief, individual freedom, and political authority. Kant’s work contained basic tensions that would continue to shape German thought—and indeed all of European philosophy—well into the 20th century.[117] German Enlightenment won the support of princes, aristocrats, and the middle classes, and it permanently reshaped the culture.[118] However, there was a conservatism among the elites that warned against going too far.[119]

In the 1780s, Lutheran ministers Johann Heinrich Schulz and Karl Wilhelm Brumbey got in trouble with their preaching as they were attacked and ridiculed by Kant, Wilhelm Abraham Teller and others. In 1788, Prussia issued an «Edict on Religion» that forbade preaching any sermon that undermined popular belief in the Holy Trinity and the Bible. The goal was to avoid skepticism, deism, and theological disputes that might impinge on domestic tranquility. Men who doubted the value of Enlightenment favoured the measure, but so too did many supporters. German universities had created a closed elite that could debate controversial issues among themselves, but spreading them to the public was seen as too risky. This intellectual elite was favoured by the state, but that might be reversed if the process of the Enlightenment proved politically or socially destabilizing.[120]

Habsburg monarchy[edit]

The reign of Maria Theresa, the first Habsburg monarch to be considered influenced by the Enlightenment in some areas, was marked by a mix of enlightenment and conservatism. Her son Joseph II’s brief reign was marked by this conflict, with his ideology of Josephinism facing opposition. Emperor Leopold II, who was an early opponent of capital punishment, had a brief and contentious rule that was mostly marked by relations with France. Similarly, Emperor Francis II’s rule was primarily marked by relations with France.

Italy[edit]

Statue of Cesare Beccaria, widely considered one of the greatest thinkers of the Age of Enlightenment.

In Italy the main centers of diffusion of the Enlightenment were Naples and Milan:[121] in both cities the intellectuals took public office and collaborated with the Bourbon and Habsburg administrations. In Naples, Antonio Genovesi, Ferdinando Galiani, and Gaetano Filangieri were active under the tolerant King Charles of Bourbon. However, the Neapolitan Enlightenment, like Vico’s philosophy, remained almost always in the theoretical field.[122] Only later, many Enlighteners animated the unfortunate experience of the Parthenopean Republic. In Milan, however, the movement strove to find concrete solutions to problems. The center of discussions was the magazine Il Caffè (1762–1766), founded by brothers Pietro and Alessandro Verri (famous philosophers and writers, as well as their brother Giovanni), who also gave life to the Accademia dei Pugni, founded in 1761. Minor centers were Tuscany, Veneto, and Piedmont, where among others, Pompeo Neri worked.

From Naples, Genovesi influenced a generation of southern Italian intellectuals and university students. His textbook Della diceosina, o sia della Filosofia del Giusto e dell’Onesto (1766) was a controversial attempt to mediate between the history of moral philosophy on the one hand and the specific problems encountered by 18th-century commercial society on the other. It contained the greater part of Genovesi’s political, philosophical, and economic thought, which became a guidebook for Neapolitan economic and social development.[123]

Science flourished as Alessandro Volta and Luigi Galvani made break-through discoveries in electricity. Pietro Verri was a leading economist in Lombardy. Historian Joseph Schumpeter states he was «the most important pre-Smithian authority on Cheapness-and-Plenty».[124] The most influential scholar on the Italian Enlightenment has been Franco Venturi.[125][126] Italy also produced some of the Enlightenment’s greatest legal theorists, including Beccaria, Giambattista Vico, and Francesco Mario Pagano.

Spain and Spanish America[edit]

When Charles II, the last Spanish Habsburg monarch, died in 1700, it touched out a major European conflict about succession and the fate of Spain and the Spanish Empire. The War of the Spanish Succession (1700–1715) brought Bourbon Prince Philip, Duke of Anjou to the throne of Spain as Philip V. Under the 1715 Treaty of Utrecht, the French and the Spanish Bourbons could not unite, with Philip renouncing any rights to the French throne. The political restriction did not impede strong French influence of the Age of Enlightenment on Spain, the Spanish monarchs, the Spanish Empire.[127][128] Philip came into effective power in 1715 and began implementing administrative reforms to try to stop the decline of the Spanish Empire.

Under Charles III, the crown began to implement serious structural changes, generally known as the Bourbon Reforms. The crown curtailed the power of the Catholic Church and the clergy, established a standing military in Spanish America, established new viceroyalties and reorganized administrative districts into intendants. Freer trade was promoted under comercio libre in which regions could trade with companies sailing from any other Spanish port, rather than the restrictive mercantile system. The crown sent out scientific expeditions to assert Spanish sovereignty over territories it claimed but did not control, but also importantly to discover the economic potential of its far-flung empire. Botanical expeditions sought plants that could be of use to the empire.[129]

One of the best acts by Charles IV, a monarch not notable for his good judgment, was to give Prussian scientist Alexander von Humboldt free rein to travel and gather information about the Spanish Empire during his five-year, self-funded expedition. Crown officials were to aid Humboldt in any way they could, so that he was able to get access to expert information. Given that Spain’s empire was closed to foreigners, Humboldt’s unfettered access is quite remarkable. His observations of New Spain, published as the Political Essay on the Kingdom of New Spain remains an important scientific and historical text.[130]

When Napoleon invaded Spain in 1808, Ferdinand VII abdicated and Napoleon placed his brother Joseph Bonaparte on the throne. To add legitimacy to this move, the Bayonne Constitution was promulgated, which included representation from Spain’s overseas components, but most Spaniards rejected the whole Napoleonic project. A war of national resistance erupted. The Cortes de Cádiz (parliament) was convened to rule Spain in the absence of the legitimate monarch, Ferdinand. It created a new governing document, the Constitution of 1812, which laid out three branches of government: executive, legislative, and judicial; put limits on the king by creating a constitutional monarchy; defined citizens as those in the Spanish Empire without African ancestry; established universal manhood suffrage; and established public education starting with primary school through university as well as freedom of expression. The constitution was in effect from 1812 until 1814, when Napoleon was defeated and Ferdinand was restored to the throne of Spain. Upon his return, Ferdinand repudiated the constitution and reestablished absolutist rule.[131]

The French invasion of Spain sparked a crisis of legitimacy of rule in Spanish America, with many regions establishing juntas to rule in the name of Ferdinand VII. Most of Spanish America fought for independence, leaving only Cuba and Puerto Rico as well as the Philippines as overseas components of the Spanish Empire until the Spanish–American War in 1898. All newly independent and sovereign nations became republics by 1824, with written constitutions. Mexico’s brief post-independence monarchy was overthrown and replaced by a federal republic under the Constitution of 1824, inspired by both the U.S. and Spanish constitutions.

Haiti[edit]

The Haitian Revolution began in 1791 and ended in 1804 and shows how Enlightenment ideas «were part of complex transcultural flows.»[3] Radical ideas in Paris during and after the French Revolution were mobilized in Haiti, such as by Toussaint L’Ouverture.[3] Toussaint had read the critique of European colonialism in Guillaume Thomas Raynal’s book Histoire des deux Indes and «was particularly impressed by Raynal’s prediction of the coming of a ‘Black Spartacus.«[3]

The revolution combined Enlightenment ideas with the experiences of the slaves in Haiti, two-thirds of whom had been born in Africa and could «draw on specific notions of kingdom and just government from Western and Central Africa, and to employ religious practices such as voodoo for the formation of revolutionary communities.»[3] The revolution also affected France and «forced the French National Convention to abolish slavery in 1794.»[3]

Portugal[edit]

The Enlightenment in Portugal (Iluminismo) was heavily marked by the rule of Prime Minister Marquis of Pombal under King Joseph I from 1756 to 1777. Following the 1755 Lisbon earthquake which destroyed a large part of Lisbon, the Marquis of Pombal implemented important economic policies to regulate commercial activity (in particular with Brazil and England), and to standardise quality throughout the country (for example by introducing the first integrated industries in Portugal). His reconstruction of Lisbon’s riverside district in straight and perpendicular streets (the Lisbon Baixa), methodically organized to facilitate commerce and exchange (for example by assigning to each street a different product or service), can be seen as a direct application of the Enlightenment ideas to governance and urbanism. His urbanistic ideas, also being the first large-scale example of earthquake engineering, became collectively known as Pombaline style, and were implemented throughout the kingdom during his stay in office. His governance was as enlightened as ruthless, see for example the Távora affair.

In literature, the first Enlightenment ideas in Portugal can be traced back to the diplomat, philosopher, and writer António Vieira[132] who spent a considerable amount of his life in colonial Brazil denouncing discriminations against New Christians and the indigenous peoples in Brazil. During the 18th century, enlightened literary movements such as the Arcádia Lusitana (lasting from 1756 until 1776, then replaced by the Nova Arcádia in 1790 until 1794) surfaced in the academic medium, in particular involving former students of the University of Coimbra. A distinct member of this group was the poet Manuel Maria Barbosa du Bocage. The physician António Nunes Ribeiro Sanches was also an important Enlightenment figure, contributing to the Encyclopédie and being part of the Russian court. The ideas of the Enlightenment influenced various economists and anti-colonial intellectuals throughout the Portuguese Empire, such as José de Azeredo Coutinho, José da Silva Lisboa, Cláudio Manoel da Costa, and Tomás Antônio Gonzaga.

The Napoleonic invasion of Portugal had consequences for the Portuguese monarchy. With the aid of the British navy, the Portuguese royal family was evacuated to Brazil, its most important colony. Even though Napoleon had been defeated, the royal court remained in Brazil. The Liberal Revolution of 1820 forced the return of the royal family to Portugal. The terms by which the restored king was to rule was a constitutional monarchy under the Constitution of Portugal. Brazil declared its independence of Portugal in 1822 and became a monarchy.

Russia[edit]

In Russia, the government began to actively encourage the proliferation of arts and sciences in the mid-18th century. This era produced the first Russian university, library, theatre, public museum, and independent press. Like other enlightened despots, Catherine the Great played a key role in fostering the arts, sciences and education. She used her own interpretation of Enlightenment ideals, assisted by notable international experts such as Voltaire (by correspondence) and in residence world class scientists such as Leonhard Euler and Peter Simon Pallas. The national Enlightenment differed from its Western European counterpart in that it promoted further modernization of all aspects of Russian life and was concerned with attacking the institution of serfdom in Russia. The Russian Enlightenment centered on the individual instead of societal enlightenment and encouraged the living of an enlightened life.[133][134] A powerful element was prosveshchenie which combined religious piety, erudition, and commitment to the spread of learning. However, it lacked the skeptical and critical spirit of the Western European Enlightenment.[135]

Poland and Lithuania[edit]

Enlightenment ideas (oświecenie) emerged late in Poland, as the Polish middle class was weaker and szlachta (nobility) culture (Sarmatism) together with the Polish–Lithuanian Commonwealth political system (Golden Liberty) were in deep crisis. The political system was built on aristocratic republicanism, but was unable to defend itself against powerful neighbors Russia, Prussia, and Austria as they repeatedly sliced off regions until nothing was left of independent Poland. The period of Polish Enlightenment began in the 1730s–1740s and especially in theatre and the arts peaked in the reign of King Stanisław August Poniatowski (second half of the 18th century).

Warsaw was a main centre after 1750, with an expansion of schools and educational institutions and the arts patronage held at the Royal Castle.[136] Leaders promoted tolerance and more education. They included King Stanislaw II August and reformers Piotr Switkowski, Antoni Poplawski, Josef Niemcewicz, and Jósef Pawlinkowski, as well as Baudouin de Cortenay, a Polonized dramatist. Opponents included Florian Jaroszewicz, Gracjan Piotrowski, Karol Wyrwicz, and Wojciech Skarszewski.[137] The movement went into decline with the Third Partition of Poland (1795) – a national tragedy inspiring a short period of sentimental writing – and ended in 1822, replaced by Romanticism.[138]

China[edit]

Eighteenth-century China experienced «a trend towards seeing fewer dragons and miracles, not unlike the disenchantment that began to spread across the Europe of the Enlightenment.»[3] Furthermore, «some of the developments that we associate with Europe’s Enlightenment resemble events in China remarkably.»[3] During this time, ideals of Chinese society were reflected in «the reign of the Qing emperors Kangxi and Qianlong; China was posited as the incarnation of an enlightened and meritocratic society—and instrumentalized for criticisms of absolutist rule in Europe.»[3]

Japan[edit]

From 1641 to 1853, the Tokugawa shogunate of Japan enforced a policy called kaikin. The policy prohibited foreign contact with most outside countries.[139] Robert Bellah found «origins of modern Japan in certain strands of Confucian thinking, a ‘functional analogue to the Protestant Ethic’ that Max Weber singled out as the driving force behind Western capitalism.»[3] Japanese Confucian and Enlightenment ideas were brought together, for example, in the work of the Japanese reformer Tsuda Mamichi in the 1870s, who said, «Whenever we open our mouths…it is to speak of ‘enlightenment.«[3]

In Japan and much of East Asia, Confucian ideas were not replaced but «ideas associated with the Enlightenment were instead fused with the existing cosmology—which in turn was refashioned under conditions of global interaction.»[3] In Japan in particular, the term ri, which is the Confucian idea of «order and harmony on human society» also came to represent «the idea of laissez-faire and the rationality of market exchange.»[3] By the 1880s, the slogan «Civilization and Enlightenment» became potent throughout Japan, China, and Korea and was employed to address challenges of globalization.[3]

Korea[edit]

During this time, Korea «aimed at isolation» and was known as the «hermit kingdom» but became awakened to Enlightenment ideas by the 1890s such as with the activities of the Independence Club.[3] Korea was influenced by China and Japan but also found its own Enlightenment path with the Korean intellectual Yu Kilchun who popularized the term Enlightenment throughout Korea.[3] The use of Enlightenment ideas was a «response to a specific situation in Korea in the 1890s, and not a belated answer to Voltaire.»[3]

India[edit]

In 18th century India, Tipu Sultan was an enlightened monarch, who «was one of the founding members of the (French) Jacobin Club in Seringapatam, had planted a liberty tree, and asked to be addressed as ‘Tipu Citoyen,» which means Citizen Tipu.[3] In parts of India, an important movement called the «Bengal Renaissance» led to Enlightenment reforms beginning in the 1820s.[3] Ram Mohan Roy was a reformer who «fused different traditions in his project of social reform that made him a proponent of a ‘religion of reason.«[3]

Egypt[edit]

Eighteenth-century Egypt had «a form of ‘cultural revival’ in the making—specifically Islamic origins of modernization long before Napoleon’s Egyptian campaign.»[3] Napoleon’s expedition into Egypt further encouraged «social transformations that harkened back to debates about inner-Islamic reform, but now were also legitimized by referring to the authority of the Enlightenment.»[3] A major intellectual influence on Islamic modernism and expanding the Enlightenment in Egypt, Rifa al-Tahtawi «oversaw the publication of hundreds of European works in the Arabic language.»[3]

Ottoman Empire[edit]

The Enlightenment began to influence the Ottoman Empire in the 1830s and continued into the late 19th century.[3]
The Tanzimat was a period of reform in the Ottoman Empire that began with the Gülhane Hatt-ı Şerif in 1839 and ended with the First Constitutional Era in 1876.

Namik Kemal, a political activist and member of the Young Ottomans, drew on major Enlightenment thinkers and «a variety of intellectual resources in his quest for social and political reform.»[3] In 1893, Kemal responded to Ernest Renan, who had indicted the Islamic religion, with his own version of the Enlightenment, which «was not a poor copy of French debates in the eighteenth century, but an original position responding to the exigencies of Ottoman society in the late nineteenth century.»[3]

Historiography[edit]

The Enlightenment has always been contested territory. According to Keith Thomas, its supporters «hail it as the source of everything that is progressive about the modern world. For them, it stands for freedom of thought, rational inquiry, critical thinking, religious tolerance, political liberty, scientific achievement, the pursuit of happiness, and hope for the future.»[140] Thomas adds that its detractors accuse it of shallow rationalism, naïve optimism, unrealistic universalism, and moral darkness. From the start, conservative and clerical defenders of traditional religion attacked materialism and skepticism as evil forces that encouraged immorality. By 1794, they pointed to the Reign of Terror during the French Revolution as confirmation of their predictions.

As the Enlightenment was ending, Romantic philosophers argued that excessive dependence on reason was a mistake perpetuated by the Enlightenment because it disregarded the bonds of history, myth, faith, and tradition that were necessary to hold society together.[141] Ritchie Robertson portrays it as a grand intellectual and political program, offering a «science» of society modeled on the powerful physical laws of Newton. «Social science» was seen as the instrument of human improvement. It would expose truth and expand human happiness.[142]

Definition[edit]

The term «Enlightenment» emerged in English in the latter part of the 19th century,[143] with particular reference to French philosophy, as the equivalent of the French term Lumières (used first by Jean-Baptiste Dubos in 1733 and already well established by 1751). From Kant’s 1784 essay «Beantwortung der Frage: Was ist Aufklärung?» («Answering the Question: What is Enlightenment?»), the German term became Aufklärung (aufklären=to illuminate; sich aufklären=to clear up). However, scholars have never agreed on a definition of the Enlightenment or on its chronological or geographical extent. Terms like les Lumières (French), illuminismo (Italian), ilustración (Spanish) and Aufklärung (German) referred to partly overlapping movements. Not until the late 19th century did English scholars agree they were talking about «the Enlightenment».[141][144]

If there is something you know, communicate it. If there is something you don’t know, search for it.

— An engraving from the 1772 edition of the Encyclopédie; Truth, in the top center, is surrounded by light and unveiled by the figures to the right, Philosophy and Reason

Enlightenment historiography began in the period itself, from what Enlightenment figures said about their work. A dominant element was the intellectual angle they took. Jean le Rond d’Alembert’s Preliminary Discourse of l’Encyclopédie provides a history of the Enlightenment which comprises a chronological list of developments in the realm of knowledge—of which the Encyclopédie forms the pinnacle.[145] In 1783, Mendelssohn referred to Enlightenment as a process by which man was educated in the use of reason.[146] Kant called Enlightenment «man’s release from his self-incurred tutelage», tutelage being «man’s inability to make use of his understanding without direction from another».[147] «For Kant, Enlightenment was mankind’s final coming of age, the emancipation of the human consciousness from an immature state of ignorance».[148] The German scholar Ernst Cassirer called the Enlightenment «a part and a special phase of that whole intellectual development through which modern philosophic thought gained its characteristic self-confidence and self-consciousness».[149] According to historian Roy Porter, the liberation of the human mind from a dogmatic state of ignorance, is the epitome of what the Age of Enlightenment was trying to capture.[150]

Bertrand Russell saw the Enlightenment as a phase in a progressive development which began in antiquity and that reason and challenges to the established order were constant ideals throughout that time.[151] Russell said that the Enlightenment was ultimately born out of the Protestant reaction against the Catholic Counter-Reformation and that philosophical views such as affinity for democracy against monarchy originated among 16th-century Protestants to justify their desire to break away from the Catholic Church. Although many of these philosophical ideals were picked up by Catholics, Russell argues that by the 18th century the Enlightenment was the principal manifestation of the schism that began with Martin Luther.[151]

Jonathan Israel rejects the attempts of postmodern and Marxian historians to understand the revolutionary ideas of the period purely as by-products of social and economic transformations.[152] He instead focuses on the history of ideas in the period from 1650 to the end of the 18th century and claims that it was the ideas themselves that caused the change that eventually led to the revolutions of the latter half of the 18th century and the early 19th century.[153] Israel argues that until the 1650s Western civilization «was based on a largely shared core of faith, tradition, and authority».[154]

Time span[edit]

There is little consensus on the precise beginning of the Age of Enlightenment, though several historians and philosophers argue that it was marked by Descartes’ 1637 philosophy of Cogito, ergo sum («I think, therefore I am»), which shifted the epistemological basis from external authority to internal certainty.[155][156][157] In France, many cited the publication of Newton’s Principia Mathematica (1687),[158] which built upon the work of earlier scientists and formulated the laws of motion and universal gravitation.[159] The middle of the 17th century (1650) or the beginning of the 18th century (1701) are often used as epochs.[citation needed] French historians usually place the Siècle des Lumières («Century of Enlightenments») between 1715 and 1789: from the beginning of the reign of Louis XV until the French Revolution.[160] Most scholars use the last years of the century, often choosing the French Revolution or the beginning of the Napoleonic Wars (1804) as a convenient point in time with which to date the end of the Enlightenment.[161]

In recent years, scholars have expanded the time span and global perspective of the Enlightenment by examining: (1) how European intellectuals did not work alone and other people helped spread and adapt Enlightenment ideas, (2) how Enlightenment ideas were «a response to cross-border interaction and global integration», and (3) how the Enlightenment «continued throughout the nineteenth century and beyond.»[3] The Enlightenment «was not merely a history of diffusion» and «was the work of historical actors around the world… who invoked the term… for their own specific purposes.»[3]

Modern study[edit]

In the 1947 book Dialectic of Enlightenment, Frankfurt School philosophers Max Horkheimer and Theodor W. Adorno argue:

Enlightenment, understood in the widest sense as the advance of thought, has always aimed at liberating human beings from fear and installing them as masters. Yet the wholly enlightened earth radiates under the sign of disaster triumphant.[162]

Extending Horkheimer and Adorno’s argument, intellectual historian Jason Josephson Storm argues that any idea of the Age of Enlightenment as a clearly defined period that is separate from the earlier Renaissance and later Romanticism or Counter-Enlightenment constitutes a myth. Storm points out that there are vastly different and mutually contradictory periodizations of the Enlightenment depending on nation, field of study, and school of thought; that the term and category of «Enlightenment» referring to the Scientific Revolution was actually applied after the fact; that the Enlightenment did not see an increase in disenchantment or the dominance of the mechanistic worldview; and that a blur in the early modern ideas of the humanities and natural sciences makes it hard to circumscribe a Scientific Revolution.[163] Storm defends his categorization of the Enlightenment as «myth» by noting the regulative role ideas of a period of Enlightenment and disenchantment play in modern Western culture, such that belief in magic, spiritualism, and even religion appears somewhat taboo in intellectual strata.[164]

In the 1970s, study of the Enlightenment expanded to include the ways Enlightenment ideas spread to European colonies and how they interacted with indigenous cultures and how the Enlightenment took place in formerly unstudied areas such as Italy, Greece, the Balkans, Poland, Hungary, and Russia.[165] Intellectuals such as Robert Darnton and Jürgen Habermas have focused on the social conditions of the Enlightenment. Habermas described the creation of the «bourgeois public sphere» in 18th-century Europe, containing the new venues and modes of communication allowing for rational exchange. Habermas said that the public sphere was bourgeois, egalitarian, rational, and independent from the state, making it the ideal venue for intellectuals to critically examine contemporary politics and society, away from the interference of established authority. While the public sphere is generally an integral component of the social study of the Enlightenment, other historians[note 3] have questioned whether the public sphere had these characteristics.

Society and culture[edit]

In contrast to the intellectual historiographical approach of the Enlightenment, which examines the various currents or discourses of intellectual thought within the European context during the 17th and 18th centuries, the cultural (or social) approach examines the changes that occurred in European society and culture. This approach studies the process of changing sociabilities and cultural practices during the Enlightenment.

One of the primary elements of the culture of the Enlightenment was the rise of the public sphere, a «realm of communication marked by new arenas of debate, more open and accessible forms of urban public space and sociability, and an explosion of print culture», in the late 17th century and 18th century.[166] Elements of the public sphere included that it was egalitarian, that it discussed the domain of «common concern», and that argument was founded on reason.[167] Habermas uses the term «common concern» to describe those areas of political/social knowledge and discussion that were previously the exclusive territory of the state and religious authorities, now open to critical examination by the public sphere. The values of this bourgeois public sphere included holding reason to be supreme, considering everything to be open to criticism (the public sphere is critical), and the opposition of secrecy of all sorts.[168]

German explorer Alexander von Humboldt showed his disgust for slavery and often criticized the colonial policies—he always acted out of a deeply humanistic conviction, borne by the ideas of the Enlightenment.[169]

The creation of the public sphere has been associated with two long-term historical trends: the rise of the modern nation state and the rise of capitalism. The modern nation state in its consolidation of public power created by counterpoint a private realm of society independent of the state, which allowed for the public sphere. Capitalism also increased society’s autonomy and self-awareness, as well as an increasing need for the exchange of information. As the nascent public sphere expanded, it embraced a large variety of institutions, and the most commonly cited were coffee houses and cafés, salons and the literary public sphere, figuratively localized in the Republic of Letters.[170] In France, the creation of the public sphere was helped by the aristocracy’s move from the king’s palace at Versailles to Paris in about 1720, since their rich spending stimulated the trade in luxuries and artistic creations, especially fine paintings.[171]

The context for the rise of the public sphere was the economic and social change commonly associated with the Industrial Revolution: «Economic expansion, increasing urbanization, rising population and improving communications in comparison to the stagnation of the previous century».[172] Rising efficiency in production techniques and communication lowered the prices of consumer goods and increased the amount and variety of goods available to consumers (including the literature essential to the public sphere). Meanwhile, the colonial experience (most European states had colonial empires in the 18th century) began to expose European society to extremely heterogeneous cultures, leading to the breaking down of «barriers between cultural systems, religious divides, gender differences and geographical areas».[173]

The word «public» implies the highest level of inclusivity—the public sphere by definition should be open to all. However, this sphere was only public to relative degrees. Enlightenment thinkers frequently contrasted their conception of the «public» with that of the people: Condorcet contrasted «opinion» with populace, Marmontel «the opinion of men of letters» with «the opinion of the multitude» and d’Alembert the «truly enlightened public» with «the blind and noisy multitude».[174] Additionally, most institutions of the public sphere excluded both women and the lower classes.[175] Cross-class influences occurred through noble and lower class participation in areas such as the coffeehouses and the Masonic lodges.

Implications in the arts[edit]

Because of the focus on reason over superstition, the Enlightenment cultivated the arts.[176] Emphasis on learning, art, and music became more widespread, especially with the growing middle class. Areas of study such as literature, philosophy, science, and the fine arts increasingly explored subject matter to which the general public, in addition to the previously more segregated professionals and patrons, could relate.[177]

As musicians depended more on public support, public concerts became increasingly popular and helped supplement performers’ and composers’ incomes. The concerts also helped them to reach a wider audience. Handel, for example, epitomized this with his highly public musical activities in London. He gained considerable fame there with performances of his operas and oratorios. The music of Haydn and Mozart, with their Viennese Classical styles, are usually regarded as being the most in line with the Enlightenment ideals.[178]

The desire to explore, record, and systematize knowledge had a meaningful impact on music publications. Rousseau’s Dictionnaire de musique (published 1767 in Geneva and 1768 in Paris) was a leading text in the late 18th century.[178] This widely available dictionary gave short definitions of words like genius and taste and was clearly influenced by the Enlightenment movement. Another text influenced by Enlightenment values was Charles Burney’s A General History of Music: From the Earliest Ages to the Present Period (1776), which was a historical survey and an attempt to rationalize elements in music systematically over time.[179] Recently, musicologists have shown renewed interest in the ideas and consequences of the Enlightenment. For example, Rose Rosengard Subotnik’s Deconstructive Variations (subtitled Music and Reason in Western Society) compares Mozart’s Die Zauberflöte (1791) using the Enlightenment and Romantic perspectives and concludes that the work is «an ideal musical representation of the Enlightenment».[179]

As the economy and the middle class expanded, there was an increasing number of amateur musicians. One manifestation of this involved women, who became more involved with music on a social level. Women were already engaged in professional roles as singers and increased their presence in the amateur performers’ scene, especially with keyboard music.[180] Music publishers begin to print music that amateurs could understand and play. The majority of the works that were published were for keyboard, voice and keyboard, and chamber ensemble.[180] After these initial genres were popularized, from the mid-century on, amateur groups sang choral music, which then became a new trend for publishers to capitalize on. The increasing study of the fine arts, as well as access to amateur-friendly published works, led to more people becoming interested in reading and discussing music. Music magazines, reviews, and critical works which suited amateurs as well as connoisseurs began to surface.[180]

Dissemination of ideas[edit]

The philosophes spent a great deal of energy disseminating their ideas among educated men and women in cosmopolitan cities. They used many venues, some of them quite new.

Republic of Letters[edit]

The term «Republic of Letters» was coined in 1664 by Pierre Bayle in his journal Nouvelles de la Republique des Lettres. Towards the end of the 18th century, the editor of Histoire de la République des Lettres en France, a literary survey, described the Republic of Letters as being:

In the midst of all the governments that decide the fate of men; in the bosom of so many states, the majority of them despotic … there exists a certain realm which holds sway only over the mind … that we honor with the name Republic, because it preserves a measure of independence, and because it is almost its essence to be free. It is the realm of talent and of thought.[181]

The Republic of Letters was the sum of a number of Enlightenment ideals: an egalitarian realm governed by knowledge that could act across political boundaries and rival state power.[181] It was a forum that supported «free public examination of questions regarding religion or legislation».[182] Kant considered written communication essential to his conception of the public sphere; once everyone was a part of the «reading public», then society could be said to be enlightened.[183] The people who participated in the Republic of Letters, such as Diderot and Voltaire, are frequently known today as important Enlightenment figures. Indeed, the men who wrote Diderot’s Encyclopédie arguably formed a microcosm of the larger «republic».[184]

Many women played an essential part in the French Enlightenment because of the role they played as salonnières in Parisian salons, as the contrast to the male philosophes. The salon was the principal social institution of the republic[185] and «became the civil working spaces of the project of Enlightenment». Women, as salonnières, were «the legitimate governors of [the] potentially unruly discourse» that took place within.[186] While women were marginalized in the public culture of the Old Regime, the French Revolution destroyed the old cultural and economic restraints of patronage and corporatism (guilds), opening French society to female participation, particularly in the literary sphere.[187]

In France, the established men of letters (gens de lettres) had fused with the elites (les grands) of French society by the mid-18th century. This led to the creation of an oppositional literary sphere, Grub Street, the domain of a «multitude of versifiers and would-be authors».[188] These men came to London to become authors only to discover that the literary market could not support large numbers of writers, who in any case were very poorly remunerated by the publishing-bookselling guilds.[189]

The writers of Grub Street, the Grub Street Hacks, were left feeling bitter about the relative success of the men of letters[190] and found an outlet for their literature which was typified by the libelle. Written mostly in the form of pamphlets, the libelles «slandered the court, the Church, the aristocracy, the academies, the salons, everything elevated and respectable, including the monarchy itself».[191] Le Gazetier cuirassé by Charles Théveneau de Morande was a prototype of the genre. It was Grub Street literature that was most read by the public during the Enlightenment.[192] According to Darnton, more importantly the Grub Street hacks inherited the «revolutionary spirit» once displayed by the philosophes and paved the way for the French Revolution by desacralizing figures of political, moral, and religious authority in France.[193]

Book industry[edit]

ESTC data 1477–1799 by decade given with a regional differentiation

The increased consumption of reading materials of all sorts was one of the key features of the «social» Enlightenment. Developments in the Industrial Revolution allowed consumer goods to be produced in greater quantities at lower prices, encouraging the spread of books, pamphlets, newspapers, and journals – «media of the transmission of ideas and attitudes». Commercial development likewise increased the demand for information, along with rising populations and increased urbanisation.[194] However, demand for reading material extended outside of the realm of the commercial and outside the realm of the upper and middle classes, as evidenced by the bibliothèque bleue. Literacy rates are difficult to gauge, but in France the rates doubled over the course of the 18th century.[195] Reflecting the decreasing influence of religion, the number of books about science and art published in Paris doubled from 1720 to 1780, while the number of books about religion dropped to just one-tenth of the total.[21]

Reading underwent serious changes in the 18th century. In particular, Rolf Engelsing has argued for the existence of a reading revolution. Until 1750, reading was done intensively: people tended to own a small number of books and read them repeatedly, often to small audience. After 1750, people began to read «extensively», finding as many books as they could, increasingly reading them alone.[196] This is supported by increasing literacy rates, particularly among women.[197]

The vast majority of the reading public could not afford to own a private library, and while most of the state-run «universal libraries» set up in the 17th and 18th centuries were open to the public, they were not the only sources of reading material. On one end of the spectrum was the bibliothèque bleue, a collection of cheaply produced books published in Troyes, France. Intended for a largely rural and semi-literate audience these books included almanacs, retellings of medieval romances and condensed versions of popular novels, among other things. While some historians have argued against the Enlightenment’s penetration into the lower classes, the bibliothèque bleue represents at least a desire to participate in Enlightenment sociability.[198] Moving up the classes, a variety of institutions offered readers access to material without needing to buy anything. Libraries that lent out their material for a small price started to appear, and occasionally bookstores would offer a small lending library to their patrons. Coffee houses commonly offered books, journals, and sometimes even popular novels to their customers. Tatler and The Spectator, two influential periodicals sold from 1709 to 1714, were closely associated with coffee house culture in London, being both read and produced in various establishments in the city.[199] This is an example of the triple or even quadruple function of the coffee house: reading material was often obtained, read, discussed, and even produced on the premises.[200]

It is difficult to determine what people actually read during the Enlightenment. For example, examining the catalogs of private libraries gives an image skewed in favor of the classes wealthy enough to afford libraries and also ignores censored works unlikely to be publicly acknowledged. For this reason, a study of publishing would be much more fruitful for discerning reading habits.[201] Across continental Europe, but in France especially, booksellers and publishers had to negotiate censorship laws of varying strictness. For example, the Encyclopédie narrowly escaped seizure and had to be saved by Malesherbes, the man in charge of the French censor. Indeed, many publishing companies were conveniently located outside France so as to avoid overzealous French censors. They would smuggle their merchandise across the border, where it would then be transported to clandestine booksellers or small-time peddlers.[202] The records of clandestine booksellers may give a better representation of what literate Frenchmen might have truly read, since their clandestine nature provided a less restrictive product choice.[203] In one case, political books were the most popular category, primarily libels and pamphlets. Readers were more interested in sensationalist stories about criminals and political corruption than they were in political theory itself. The second most popular category, «general works» (those books «that did not have a dominant motif and that contained something to offend almost everyone in authority»), demonstrated a high demand for generally low-brow subversive literature. However, these works never became part of literary canon and are largely forgotten today as a result.[203]

A healthy, legal publishing industry existed throughout Europe, although established publishers and book sellers occasionally ran afoul of the law. For example, the Encyclopédie condemned by both the King and Clement XII, nevertheless found its way into print with the help of the aforementioned Malesherbes and creative use of French censorship law.[204] However, many works were sold without running into any legal trouble at all. Borrowing records from libraries in England, Germany, and North America indicate that more than 70% of books borrowed were novels. Less than 1% of the books were of a religious nature, indicating the general trend of declining religiosity.[181]

Natural history[edit]

Georges Buffon is best remembered for his Histoire naturelle, a 44 volume encyclopedia describing everything known about the natural world

A genre that greatly rose in importance was that of scientific literature. Natural history in particular became increasingly popular among the upper classes. Works of natural history include René-Antoine Ferchault de Réaumur’s Histoire naturelle des insectes and Jacques Gautier d’Agoty’s La Myologie complète, ou description de tous les muscles du corps humain (1746). Outside Ancien Régime France, natural history was an important part of medicine and industry, encompassing the fields of botany, zoology, meteorology, hydrology, and mineralogy. Students in Enlightenment universities and academies were taught these subjects to prepare them for careers as diverse as medicine and theology. As shown by Matthew Daniel Eddy, natural history in this context was a very middle class pursuit and operated as a fertile trading zone for the interdisciplinary exchange of diverse scientific ideas.[205]

The target audience of natural history was French upper class, evidenced more by the specific discourse of the genre than by the generally high prices of its works. Naturalists catered to upper class desire for erudition: many texts had an explicit instructive purpose. However, natural history was often a political affair. As Emma Spary writes, the classifications used by naturalists «slipped between the natural world and the social … to establish not only the expertise of the naturalists over the natural, but also the dominance of the natural over the social».[206] The idea of taste (le goût) was a social indicator: to truly be able to categorize nature, one had to have the proper taste, an ability of discretion shared by all members of the upper class. In this way, natural history spread many of the scientific developments of the time but also provided a new source of legitimacy for the dominant class.[207] From this basis, naturalists could then develop their own social ideals based on their scientific works.[208]

Scientific and literary journals[edit]

The first scientific and literary journals were established during the Enlightenment. The first journal, the Parisian Journal des sçavans, appeared in 1665. However, it was not until 1682 that periodicals began to be more widely produced. French and Latin were the dominant languages of publication, but there was also a steady demand for material in German and Dutch. There was generally low demand for English publications on the continent, which was echoed by England’s similar lack of desire for French works. Languages commanding less of an international market—such as Danish, Spanish, and Portuguese—found journal success more difficult, and a more international language was used instead. French slowly took over Latin’s status as the lingua franca of learned circles. This in turn gave precedence to the publishing industry in Holland, where the vast majority of these French language periodicals were produced.[209]

Jonathan Israel called the journals the most influential cultural innovation of European intellectual culture.[210] They shifted the attention of the «cultivated public» away from established authorities to novelty and innovation, and instead promoted the Enlightened ideals of toleration and intellectual objectivity. Being a source of knowledge derived from science and reason, they were an implicit critique of existing notions of universal truth monopolized by monarchies, parliaments, and religious authorities. They also advanced Christian Enlightenment that upheld «the legitimacy of God-ordained authority»—the Bible—in which there had to be agreement between the biblical and natural theories.[211]

Encyclopedias and dictionaries[edit]

First page of the Encyclopédie, published between 1751 and 1766

Although the existence of dictionaries and encyclopedias spanned into ancient times, the texts changed from defining words in a long running list to far more detailed discussions of those words in 18th-century encyclopedic dictionaries.[212] The works were part of an Enlightenment movement to systematize knowledge and provide education to a wider audience than the elite. As the 18th century progressed, the content of encyclopedias also changed according to readers’ tastes. Volumes tended to focus more strongly on secular affairs, particularly science and technology, rather than matters of theology.

Along with secular matters, readers also favoured an alphabetical ordering scheme over cumbersome works arranged along thematic lines.[213] Commenting on alphabetization, the historian Charles Porset has said that «as the zero degree of taxonomy, alphabetical order authorizes all reading strategies; in this respect it could be considered an emblem of the Enlightenment». For Porset, the avoidance of thematic and hierarchical systems thus allows free interpretation of the works and becomes an example of egalitarianism.[214] Encyclopedias and dictionaries also became more popular during the Age of Enlightenment as the number of educated consumers who could afford such texts began to multiply.[212] In the latter half of the 18th century, the number of dictionaries and encyclopedias published by decade increased from 63 between 1760 and 1769 to approximately 148 in the decade proceeding the French Revolution.[215] Along with growth in numbers, dictionaries and encyclopedias also grew in length, often having multiple print runs that sometimes included in supplemented editions.[213]

The first technical dictionary was drafted by John Harris and entitled Lexicon Technicum: Or, An Universal English Dictionary of Arts and Sciences. Harris’ book avoids theological and biographical entries and instead concentrates on science and technology. Published in 1704, the Lexicon Technicum was the first book to be written in English that took a methodical approach to describing mathematics and commercial arithmetic along with the physical sciences and navigation. Other technical dictionaries followed Harris’ model, including Ephraim Chambers’ Cyclopaedia (1728), which included five editions and is a substantially larger work than Harris’. The folio edition of the work even included foldout engravings. The Cyclopaedia emphasized Newtonian theories, Lockean philosophy and contained thorough examinations of technologies, such as engraving, brewing, and dyeing.

In Germany, practical reference works intended for the uneducated majority became popular in the 18th century. The Marperger Curieuses Natur-, Kunst-, Berg-, Gewerk- und Handlungs-Lexicon (1712) explained terms that usefully described the trades and scientific and commercial education. Jablonksi Allgemeines Lexicon (1721) was better known than the Handlungs-Lexicon and underscored technical subjects rather than scientific theory. For example, over five columns of text were dedicated to wine while geometry and logic were allocated only twenty-two and seventeen lines, respectively. The first edition of the Encyclopædia Britannica (1771) was modelled along the same lines as the German lexicons.[216]

However, the prime example of reference works that systematized scientific knowledge in the Age of Enlightenment were universal encyclopedias rather than technical dictionaries. It was the goal of universal encyclopedias to record all human knowledge in a comprehensive reference work.[217] The most well-known of these works is Diderot and d’Alembert’s Encyclopédie, ou dictionnaire raisonné des sciences, des arts et des métiers. The work, which began publication in 1751, was composed of 35 volumes and over 71,000 separate entries. A great number of the entries were dedicated to describing the sciences and crafts in detail and provided intellectuals across Europe with a high-quality survey of human knowledge. In d’Alembert’s Preliminary Discourse to the Encyclopedia of Diderot, the work’s goal to record the extent of human knowledge in the arts and sciences is outlined:

As an Encyclopédie, it is to set forth as well as possible the order and connection of the parts of human knowledge. As a Reasoned Dictionary of the Sciences, Arts, and Trades, it is to contain the general principles that form the basis of each science and each art, liberal or mechanical, and the most essential facts that make up the body and substance of each.[218]

The massive work was arranged according to a «tree of knowledge». The tree reflected the marked division between the arts and sciences, which was largely a result of the rise of empiricism. Both areas of knowledge were united by philosophy, or the trunk of the tree of knowledge. The Enlightenment’s desacrilization of religion was pronounced in the tree’s design, particularly where theology accounted for a peripheral branch, with black magic as a close neighbour.[219] As the Encyclopédie gained popularity, it was published in quarto and octavo editions after 1777. The quarto and octavo editions were much less expensive than previous editions, making the Encyclopédie more accessible to the non-elite. Robert Darnton estimates that there were approximately 25,000 copies of the Encyclopédie in circulation throughout France and Europe before the French Revolution.[220] The extensive yet affordable encyclopedia came to represent the transmission of Enlightenment and scientific education to an expanding audience.[221]

Popularization of science[edit]

One of the most important developments that the Enlightenment era brought to the discipline of science was its popularization. An increasingly literate population seeking knowledge and education in both the arts and the sciences drove the expansion of print culture and the dissemination of scientific learning. The new literate population was precipitated by a high rise in the availability of food; this enabled many people to rise out of poverty, and instead of paying more for food, they had money for education.[222] Popularization was generally part of an overarching Enlightenment ideal that endeavoured «to make information available to the greatest number of people».[223] As public interest in natural philosophy grew during the 18th century, public lecture courses and the publication of popular texts opened up new roads to money and fame for amateurs and scientists who remained on the periphery of universities and academies.[224] More formal works included explanations of scientific theories for individuals lacking the educational background to comprehend the original scientific text. Newton’s celebrated Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica was published in Latin and remained inaccessible to readers without education in the classics until Enlightenment writers began to translate and analyze the text in the vernacular.

The first significant work that expressed scientific theory and knowledge expressly for the laity, in the vernacular and with the entertainment of readers in mind, was Bernard de Fontenelle’s Conversations on the Plurality of Worlds (1686). The book was produced specifically for women with an interest in scientific writing and inspired a variety of similar works.[225] These popular works were written in a discursive style, which was laid out much more clearly for the reader than the complicated articles, treatises, and books published by the academies and scientists. Charles Leadbetter’s Astronomy (1727) was advertised as «a Work entirely New» that would include «short and easie [sic] Rules and Astronomical Tables».[226]

The first French introduction to Newtonianism and the Principia was Eléments de la philosophie de Newton, published by Voltaire in 1738.[227] Émilie du Châtelet’s translation of the Principia, published after her death in 1756, also helped to spread Newton’s theories beyond scientific academies and the university.[228] Writing for a growing female audience, Francesco Algarotti published Il Newtonianism per le dame, which was a tremendously popular work and was translated from Italian into English by Elizabeth Carter. A similar introduction to Newtonianism for women was produced by Henry Pemberton. His A View of Sir Isaac Newton’s Philosophy was published by subscription. Extant records of subscribers show that women from a wide range of social standings purchased the book, indicating the growing number of scientifically inclined female readers among the middling class.[229] During the Enlightenment, women also began producing popular scientific works. Sarah Trimmer wrote a successful natural history textbook for children titled The Easy Introduction to the Knowledge of Nature (1782), which was published for many years in eleven editions.[230]

Schools and universities[edit]

Most work on the Enlightenment emphasizes the ideals discussed by intellectuals, rather than the actual state of education at the time. Leading educational theorists like England’s John Locke and Switzerland’s Jean Jacques Rousseau both emphasized the importance of shaping young minds early. By the late Enlightenment, there was a rising demand for a more universal approach to education, particularly after the American Revolution and the French Revolution.

The predominant educational psychology from the 1750s onward, especially in northern European countries, was associationism: the notion that the mind associates or dissociates ideas through repeated routines. In addition to being conducive to Enlightenment ideologies of liberty, self-determination, and personal responsibility, it offered a practical theory of the mind that allowed teachers to transform longstanding forms of print and manuscript culture into effective graphic tools of learning for the lower and middle orders of society.[231] Children were taught to memorize facts through oral and graphic methods that originated during the Renaissance.[232]

Many of the leading universities associated with Enlightenment progressive principles were located in northern Europe, with the most renowned being the universities of Leiden, Göttingen, Halle, Montpellier, Uppsala, and Edinburgh. These universities, especially Edinburgh, produced professors whose ideas had a significant impact on Britain’s North American colonies and later the American Republic. Within the natural sciences, Edinburgh’s medical school also led the way in chemistry, anatomy, and pharmacology.[233] In other parts of Europe, the universities and schools of France and most of Europe were bastions of traditionalism and were not hospitable to the Enlightenment. In France, the major exception was the medical university at Montpellier.[234]

Learned academies[edit]

Louis XIV visiting the Académie des sciences in 1671: «It is widely accepted that ‘modern science’ arose in the Europe of the 17th century, introducing a new understanding of the natural world»—Peter Barrett[235]

Antoine Lavoisier conducting an experiment related to combustion generated by amplified sun light

The history of Academies in France during the Enlightenment begins with the Academy of Science, founded in 1635 in Paris. It was closely tied to the French state, acting as an extension of a government seriously lacking in scientists. It helped promote and organize new disciplines and it trained new scientists. It also contributed to the enhancement of scientists’ social status, considering them to be the «most useful of all citizens». Academies demonstrate the rising interest in science along with its increasing secularization, as evidenced by the small number of clerics who were members (13%).[236] The presence of the French academies in the public sphere cannot be attributed to their membership, as although the majority of their members were bourgeois, the exclusive institution was only open to elite Parisian scholars. They perceived themselves as «interpreters of the sciences for the people». For example, it was with this in mind that academicians took it upon themselves to disprove the popular pseudo-science of mesmerism.[237]

The strongest contribution of the French Academies to the public sphere comes from the concours académiques (roughly translated as «academic contests») they sponsored throughout France. These academic contests were perhaps the most public of any institution during the Enlightenment.[238] The practice of contests dated back to the Middle Ages and was revived in the mid-17th century. The subject matter had previously been generally religious and/or monarchical, featuring essays, poetry, and painting. However, by roughly 1725 this subject matter had radically expanded and diversified, including «royal propaganda, philosophical battles, and critical ruminations on the social and political institutions of the Old Regime». Topics of public controversy were also discussed such as the theories of Newton and Descartes, the slave trade, women’s education, and justice in France.[239] More importantly, the contests were open to all, and the enforced anonymity of each submission guaranteed that neither gender nor social rank would determine the judging. Indeed, although the «vast majority» of participants belonged to the wealthier strata of society («the liberal arts, the clergy, the judiciary and the medical profession»), there were some cases of the popular classes submitting essays and even winning.[240] Similarly, a significant number of women participated—and won—the competitions. Of a total of 2,300 prize competitions offered in France, women won 49—perhaps a small number by modern standards but very significant in an age in which most women did not have any academic training. Indeed, the majority of the winning entries were for poetry competitions, a genre commonly stressed in women’s education.[241]

In England, the Royal Society of London played a significant role in the public sphere and the spread of Enlightenment ideas. It was founded by a group of independent scientists and given a royal charter in 1662.[242] The society played a large role in spreading Robert Boyle’s experimental philosophy around Europe and acted as a clearinghouse for intellectual correspondence and exchange.[243] Boyle was «a founder of the experimental world in which scientists now live and operate» and his method based knowledge on experimentation, which had to be witnessed to provide proper empirical legitimacy. This is where the Royal Society came into play: witnessing had to be a «collective act» and the Royal Society’s assembly rooms were ideal locations for relatively public demonstrations.[244] However, not just any witness was considered to be credible: «Oxford professors were accounted more reliable witnesses than Oxfordshire peasants». Two factors were taken into account: a witness’s knowledge in the area and a witness’s «moral constitution». In other words, only civil society were considered for Boyle’s public.[245]

Salons[edit]

Salons were places where philosophes were reunited and discussed old, actual, or new ideas. This led to salons being the birthplace of intellectual and enlightened ideas.

Coffeehouses[edit]

Coffeehouses were especially important to the spread of knowledge during the Enlightenment because they created a unique environment in which people from many different walks of life gathered and shared ideas. They were frequently criticized by nobles who feared the possibility of an environment in which class and its accompanying titles and privileges were disregarded. Such an environment was especially intimidating to monarchs who derived much of their power from the disparity between classes of people. If classes were to join under the influence of Enlightenment thinking, they might recognize the all-encompassing oppression and abuses of their monarchs and because of their size might be able to carry out successful revolts. Monarchs also resented the idea of their subjects convening as one to discuss political matters, especially those concerning foreign affairs—rulers thought political affairs to be their business only, a result of their supposed divine right to rule.[246]

Coffeeshops became homes away from home for many who sought to engage in discourse with their neighbors and discuss intriguing and thought-provoking matters, especially those regarding philosophy to politics. Coffeehouses were essential to the Enlightenment, for they were centers of free-thinking and self-discovery. Although many coffeehouse patrons were scholars, a great deal were not. Coffeehouses attracted a diverse set of people, including the educated wealthy and members of the bourgeoisie and the lower class. While it may seem positive that patrons, being doctors, lawyers, merchants, etc. represented almost all classes, the coffeeshop environment sparked fear in those who sought to preserve class distinction. One of the most popular critiques of the coffeehouse claimed that it «allowed promiscuous association among people from different rungs of the social ladder, from the artisan to the aristocrat» and was therefore compared to Noah’s Ark, receiving all types of animals, clean or unclean.[247] This unique culture served as a catalyst for journalism when Joseph Addison and Richard Steele recognized its potential as an audience. Together, Steele and Addison published The Spectator (1711), a daily publication which aimed, through fictional narrator Mr. Spectator, both to entertain and to provoke discussion regarding serious philosophical matters.

The first English coffeehouse opened in Oxford in 1650. Brian Cowan said that Oxford coffeehouses developed into «penny universities», offering a locus of learning that was less formal than structured institutions. These penny universities occupied a significant position in Oxford academic life, as they were frequented by those consequently referred to as the virtuosi, who conducted their research on some of the resulting premises. According to Cowan, «the coffeehouse was a place for like-minded scholars to congregate, to read, as well as learn from and to debate with each other, but was emphatically not a university institution, and the discourse there was of a far different order than any university tutorial».[248]

The Café Procope was established in Paris in 1686, and by the 1720s there were around 400 cafés in the city. The Café Procope in particular became a center of Enlightenment, welcoming such celebrities as Voltaire and Rousseau. The Café Procope was where Diderot and D’Alembert decided to create the Encyclopédie.[249] The cafés were one of the various «nerve centers» for bruits publics, public noise or rumour. These bruits were allegedly a much better source of information than were the actual newspapers available at the time.[250]

Debating societies[edit]

The debating societies are an example of the public sphere during the Enlightenment.[251] Their origins include:

  • Clubs of fifty or more men who, at the beginning of the 18th century, met in pubs to discuss religious issues and affairs of state.
  • Mooting clubs, set up by law students to practice rhetoric.
  • Spouting clubs, established to help actors train for theatrical roles.
  • John Henley’s Oratory, which mixed outrageous sermons with even more absurd questions, like «Whether Scotland be anywhere in the world?».[252]

An example of a French salon

In the late 1770s, popular debating societies began to move into more «genteel» rooms, a change which helped establish a new standard of sociability.[253] The backdrop to these developments was «an explosion of interest in the theory and practice of public elocution». The debating societies were commercial enterprises that responded to this demand, sometimes very successfully. Some societies welcomed from 800 to 1,200 spectators per night.[254]

The debating societies discussed an extremely wide range of topics. Before the Enlightenment, most intellectual debates revolved around «confessional»—that is, Catholic, Lutheran, Reformed (Calvinist) or Anglican issues, and the main aim of these debates was to establish which bloc of faith ought to have the «monopoly of truth and a God-given title to authority».[255] After this date, everything thus previously rooted in tradition was questioned and often replaced by new concepts in the light of philosophical reason. After the second half of the 17th century and during the 18th century, a «general process of rationalization and secularization set in» and confessional disputes were reduced to a secondary status in favor of the «escalating contest between faith and incredulity».[255]

In addition to debates on religion, societies discussed issues such as politics and the role of women. However, the critical subject matter of these debates did not necessarily translate into opposition to the government; the results of the debate quite frequently upheld the status quo.[256] From a historical standpoint, one of the most important features of the debating society was their openness to the public, as women attended and even participated in almost every debating society, which were likewise open to all classes providing they could pay the entrance fee. Once inside, spectators were able to participate in a largely egalitarian form of sociability that helped spread Enlightenment ideas.[257]

Masonic lodges[edit]

Masonic initiation ceremony

Historians have long debated the extent to which the secret network of Freemasonry was a main factor in the Enlightenment.[258] The leaders of the Enlightenment included Freemasons such as Diderot, Montesquieu, Voltaire, Lessing, Pope,[259] Horace Walpole, Sir Robert Walpole, Mozart, Goethe, Frederick the Great, Benjamin Franklin[260] and George Washington.[261] Norman Davies said that Freemasonry was a powerful force on behalf of liberalism in Europe from about 1700 to the twentieth century. It expanded rapidly during the Age of Enlightenment, reaching practically every country in Europe. It was especially attractive to powerful aristocrats and politicians as well as intellectuals, artists, and political activists.[262]

During the Age of Enlightenment, Freemasons comprised an international network of like-minded men, often meeting in secret in ritualistic programs at their lodges. They promoted the ideals of the Enlightenment and helped diffuse these values across Britain, France, and other places. Freemasonry as a systematic creed with its own myths, values, and set of rituals originated in Scotland c. 1600 and spread first to England and then across the Continent in the eighteenth century. They fostered new codes of conduct—including a communal understanding of liberty and equality inherited from guild sociability—»liberty, fraternity, and equality».[263] Scottish soldiers and Jacobite Scots brought to the Continent ideals of fraternity which reflected not the local system of Scottish customs but the institutions and ideals originating in the English Revolution against royal absolutism.[264] Freemasonry was particularly prevalent in France—by 1789, there were perhaps as many as 100,000 French Masons, making Freemasonry the most popular of all Enlightenment associations.[265] The Freemasons displayed a passion for secrecy and created new degrees and ceremonies. Similar societies, partially imitating Freemasonry, emerged in France, Germany, Sweden, and Russia. One example was the Illuminati founded in Bavaria in 1776, which was copied after the Freemasons, but was never part of the movement. The Illuminati was an overtly political group, which most Masonic lodges decidedly were not.[266]

Masonic lodges created a private model for public affairs. They «reconstituted the polity and established a constitutional form of self-government, complete with constitutions and laws, elections, and representatives». In other words, the micro-society set up within the lodges constituted a normative model for society as a whole. This was especially true on the continent: when the first lodges began to appear in the 1730s, their embodiment of British values was often seen as threatening by state authorities. For example, the Parisian lodge that met in the mid 1720s was composed of English Jacobite exiles.[267] Furthermore, freemasons all across Europe explicitly linked themselves to the Enlightenment as a whole. For example, in French lodges the line «As the means to be enlightened I search for the enlightened» was a part of their initiation rites. British lodges assigned themselves the duty to «initiate the unenlightened». This did not necessarily link lodges to the irreligious, but neither did this exclude them from the occasional heresy. In fact, many lodges praised the Grand Architect, the masonic terminology for the deistic divine being who created a scientifically ordered universe.[268]

German historian Reinhart Koselleck claimed: «On the Continent there were two social structures that left a decisive imprint on the Age of Enlightenment: the Republic of Letters and the Masonic lodges».[269] Scottish professor Thomas Munck argues that «although the Masons did promote international and cross-social contacts which were essentially non-religious and broadly in agreement with enlightened values, they can hardly be described as a major radical or reformist network in their own right».[270] Many of the Masons values seemed to greatly appeal to Enlightenment values and thinkers. Diderot discusses the link between Freemason ideals and the enlightenment in D’Alembert’s Dream, exploring masonry as a way of spreading enlightenment beliefs.[271] Historian Margaret Jacob stresses the importance of the Masons in indirectly inspiring enlightened political thought.[272] On the negative side, Daniel Roche contests claims that Masonry promoted egalitarianism and he argues that the lodges only attracted men of similar social backgrounds.[273] The presence of noble women in the French «lodges of adoption» that formed in the 1780s was largely due to the close ties shared between these lodges and aristocratic society.[274]

The major opponent of Freemasonry was the Roman Catholic Church so that in countries with a large Catholic element, such as France, Italy, Spain, and Mexico, much of the ferocity of the political battles involve the confrontation between what Davies calls the reactionary Church and enlightened Freemasonry.[275][276] Even in France, Masons did not act as a group.[277] American historians, while noting that Benjamin Franklin and George Washington were indeed active Masons, have downplayed the importance of Freemasonry in causing the American Revolution because the Masonic order was non-political and included both Patriots and their enemy the Loyalists.[278]

Art[edit]

The art produced during the Enlightenment focused on a search for morality that was absent from the art in previous eras.[citation needed] At the same time, the Classical art of Greece and Rome became interesting to people again, since archaeological teams discovered Pompeii and Herculaneum.[279] People took inspiration from it and revived classical art into neo-classical art. This can especially be seen in early American art and architecture, which featured arches, goddesses, and other classical architectural designs.

See also[edit]

  • Atlantic Revolutions
  • Early modern philosophy
  • European and American voyages of scientific exploration
  • Midlands Enlightenment
  • Regional Enlightenments:
    • American Enlightenment
    • Haskalah, Jewish Enlightenment
    • Modern Greek Enlightenment
    • Polish Enlightenment
    • Russian Enlightenment
    • Scottish Enlightenment
    • Spanish Enlightenment
  • Renaissance philosophy
  • Whig history
  • Witch trials in the early modern period
    • Beyond the witch trials

Notes[edit]

  1. ^ Back row, left to right: Jean-Baptiste-Louis Gresset, Pierre de Marivaux, Jean-François Marmontel, Joseph-Marie Vien, Antoine Léonard Thomas, Charles Marie de La Condamine, Guillaume Thomas François Raynal, Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Jean-Philippe Rameau, La Clairon, Charles-Jean-François Hénault, Étienne François, duc de Choiseul, a bust of Voltaire, Charles-Augustin de Ferriol d’Argental, Jean François de Saint-Lambert, Edmé Bouchardon, Jacques-Germain Soufflot, Jean-Baptiste Bourguignon d’Anville, Anne Claude de Caylus, Fortunato Felice, François Quesnay, Denis Diderot, Anne-Robert-Jacques Turgot, Baron de Laune, Chrétien Guillaume de Lamoignon de Malesherbes, Armand de Vignerot du Plessis, Pierre Louis Maupertuis, Jean-Jacques Dortous de Mairan, Henri François d’Aguesseau, Alexis Clairaut.
    Front row, right to left: Montesquieu, Sophie d’Houdetot, Claude Joseph Vernet, Bernard Le Bouyer de Fontenelle, Marie-Thérèse Rodet Geoffrin, Louis François, Prince of Conti, Marie Louise Nicole Élisabeth de La Rochefoucauld, Duchesse d’Anville, Philippe Jules François Mancini, François-Joachim de Pierre de Bernis, Claude Prosper Jolyot de Crébillon, Alexis Piron, Charles Pinot Duclos, Claude-Adrien Helvétius, Charles-André van Loo, Jean le Rond d’Alembert, Lekain at the desk reading aloud, Jeanne Julie Éléonore de Lespinasse, Anne-Marie du Boccage, René Antoine Ferchault de Réaumur, Françoise de Graffigny, Étienne Bonnot de Condillac, Bernard de Jussieu, Louis-Jean-Marie Daubenton, Georges-Louis Charles Leclerc, Comte de Buffon.
  2. ^ French: le Siècle des Lumières, lit. ‘the Century of Lights’; German: Aufklärung, «Enlightenment»; Italian: L’Illuminismo, «Enlightenment»; Polish: Oświecenie, «Enlightenment»; Portuguese: Iluminismo, «Enlightenment»; Spanish: La Ilustración, «Enlightenment»[1]
  3. ^ For example, Robert Darnton, Roger Chartier, Brian Cowan, Donna T. Andrew.

References[edit]

Citations[edit]

  1. ^ «Enlightenment», Encyclopædia Britannica, Encyclopædia Britannica Online, Encyclopædia Britannica Inc., 2016, retrieved 13 June 2016
  2. ^ «The Age of Enlightenment: A History From Beginning to chop and daisy mwah Chapter 3». publishinghau5.com. Archived from the original on 3 March 2017. Retrieved 3 April 2017.{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: unfit URL (link)
  3. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p q r s t u v w x y z aa ab Conrad, Sebastian (1 October 2012). «Enlightenment in Global History: A Historiographical Critique». The American Historical Review. 117 (4): 999–1027. doi:10.1093/ahr/117.4.999. ISSN 0002-8762.
  4. ^ Outram, Dorinda (2006), Panorama of the Enlightenment, Getty Publications, p. 29, ISBN 978-0892368617
  5. ^ Zafirovski, Milan (2010), The Enlightenment and Its Effects on Modern Society, p. 144
  6. ^ a b Rashidov, Zaur (15 December 2022). «The philosophy of Azerbaijan Enlightenment in the studies of Enver Akhmedov: a critical analysis» (PDF). Metafizika Journal (in Azerbaijani). 5 (4): 54–76. eISSN 2617-751X. ISSN 2616-6879. OCLC 1117709579. Archived from the original (PDF) on 28 January 2023. Retrieved 14 October 2022.{{cite journal}}: CS1 maint: date and year (link)
  7. ^ Eugen Weber, Movements, Currents, Trends: Aspects of European Thought in the Nineteenth and Twentieth Centuries (1992).
  8. ^ Eddy, Matthew Daniel (2022). Media and the Mind: Art, Science and Notebooks as Paper Machines, 1700-1830. University of Chicago Press.
  9. ^ Gay, Peter (1996), The Enlightenment: An Interpretation, W.W. Norton & Company, ISBN 0-393-00870-3
  10. ^ Vottari, Giuseppe (2003). L’illuminismo. Un percorso alfabetico nell’età delle riforme. Alpha Test. p. 54. ISBN 978-88-483-0456-6.
  11. ^ Maddaloni, Domenico (17 November 2011). Visioni in movimento. Teorie dell’evoluzione e scienze sociali dall’Illuminismo a oggi: Teorie dell’evoluzione e scienze sociali dall’Illuminismo a oggi. FrancoAngeli. p. 20. ISBN 978-88-568-7115-9.
  12. ^ I. Bernard Cohen, «Scientific Revolution and Creativity in the Enlightenment.» Eighteenth-Century Life 7.2 (1982): 41–54.
  13. ^ Sootin, Harry. Isaac Newton. New York: Messner (1955)
  14. ^ a b Jeremy Black, «Ancien Regime and Enlightenment. Some Recent Writing on Seventeenth-and Eighteenth-Century Europe,» European History Quarterly 22.2 (1992): 247–55.
  15. ^ Robert Darnton, The Business of Enlightenment: a publishing history of the Encyclopédie, 1775–1800 (2009).
  16. ^ The Dream of Enlightenment: The Rise of Modern Philosophy. W. W. Norton & Company. 30 August 2016. ISBN 9781631492082.
  17. ^ Israel 2006, p. 15.
  18. ^ Israel 2010, pp. vii–viii, 19.
  19. ^ Israel 2010, p. 11.
  20. ^ «Enlightenment – Definition, History, & Facts». Encyclopedia Britannica.
  21. ^ a b Petitfils 2005, pp. 99–105.
  22. ^ a b Denby, David (11 October 2004), «Northern Lights: How modern life emerged from eighteenth-century Edinburgh», The New Yorker, archived from the original on 6 June 2011
  23. ^ Barroso, José Manuel (28 November 2006), The Scottish enlightenment and the challenges for Europe in the 21st century; climate change and energy
  24. ^ «Kant’s essay What is Enlightenment?». mnstate.edu. Archived from the original on 17 February 2020. Retrieved 4 November 2015.
  25. ^ Manfred Kuehn, Kant: A Biography (2001).
  26. ^ Kreis, Steven (13 April 2012). «Mary Wollstonecraft, 1759–1797». Historyguide.org. Archived from the original on 11 January 2014. Retrieved 14 January 2014.
  27. ^ Mary Wollstonecraft, A Vindication of the Rights of Woman (Renascence Editions, 2000) online
  28. ^ Bruce P. Lenman, Integration and Enlightenment: Scotland, 1746–1832 (1993) excerpt and text search
  29. ^ Sarmant, Thierry, Histoire de Paris, p. 120.
  30. ^ Porter (2003), 79–80.
  31. ^ Burns (2003), entry: 7,103.
  32. ^ Gillispie, (1980), p. xix.
  33. ^ James E. McClellan III, «Learned Societies,» in Encyclopedia of the Enlightenment, ed. Alan Charles Kors (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003) «Oxford University Press: Encyclopedia of the Enlightenment: Alan Charles Kors». Archived from the original on 30 March 2012. Retrieved 16 October 2015. (accessed on 8 June 2008).
  34. ^ Porter, (2003), p. 91.
  35. ^ See Gillispie, (1980), «Conclusion.»
  36. ^ Porter, (2003), p. 90.
  37. ^ see Hall (1954), iii; Mason (1956), 223.
  38. ^ Burns, (2003), entry: 158.
  39. ^ Thomson, (1786), p. 203.
  40. ^ M. Magnusson (10 November 2003), «Review of James Buchan, Capital of the Mind: how Edinburgh Changed the World«, New Statesman, archived from the original on 6 June 2011, retrieved 27 April 2014
  41. ^ Swingewood, Alan (1970). «Origins of Sociology: The Case of the Scottish Enlightenment». The British Journal of Sociology. 21 (2): 164–180. doi:10.2307/588406. JSTOR 588406.
  42. ^ D. Daiches, P. Jones and J. Jones, A Hotbed of Genius: The Scottish Enlightenment, 1730–1790 (1986).
  43. ^ M. Fry, Adam Smith’s Legacy: His Place in the Development of Modern Economics (Routledge, 1992).
  44. ^ The Illusion of Free Markets, Bernard E. Harcourt, p. 260, notes 11–14.
  45. ^ «The Enlightenment throughout Europe». History-world.org. Archived from the original on 23 January 2013. Retrieved 25 March 2013.{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: unfit URL (link)
  46. ^ Roland Sarti, Italy: A Reference Guide from the Renaissance to the Present, Infobase Publishing, 2009, p. 457
  47. ^ Daniel Brewer, The Enlightenment Past: reconstructing eighteenth-century French thought (2008), p. 1
  48. ^ De Dijn, Annelien (2012). «The Politics of Enlightenment: From Peter Gay to Jonathan Israel». Historical Journal. 55 (3): 785–805. doi:10.1017/s0018246x12000301. S2CID 145439970.
  49. ^ von Guttner, Darius (2015). The French Revolution. Nelson Cengage. pp. 34–35.[permanent dead link]
  50. ^ Robert A. Ferguson, The American Enlightenment, 1750–1820 (1994).
  51. ^ «John Locke > The Influence of John Locke’s Works (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)». Plato.stanford.edu. Retrieved 14 January 2014.
  52. ^ Pierre Manent, An Intellectual History of Liberalism (1994) pp. 20–38
  53. ^ Lessnoff, Michael H. Social Contract Theory. New York: NYU, 1990. Print.[page needed]
  54. ^ Discourse on the Origin of Inequality
  55. ^ Rand, B. (1900), The Life, Unpublished Letters and Philosophical Regimen of Anthony, Earl of Shaftesbury, p. 353 quoted in Porter, Roy (2000), Enlightenment, Britain and the Creation of the Modern World, Allen Lane, The Penguin Press, p. 3
  56. ^ Lorraine Y. Landry, Marx and the postmodernism debates: an agenda for critical theory (2000) p. 7
  57. ^ Of the Original Contract
  58. ^ Eltis, David; Walvin, James, eds. (1981). The Abolition of the Atlantic Slave Trade. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press. p. 76.
  59. ^ Northrup, David, ed. (2002). The Atlantic Slave Trade. Boston: Houghton Mifflin. p. 200.
  60. ^ David Williams, ed. (1994). Voltaire: Political Writings. pp. xiv–xv. ISBN 978-0-521-43727-1.
  61. ^ Stephen J. Lee, Aspects of European history, 1494–1789 (1990) pp. 258–266
  62. ^ Nicholas Henderson, «Joseph II», History Today (March 1991) 41:21–27
  63. ^ John Stanley, «Towards A New Nation: The Enlightenment and National Revival in Poland», Canadian Review of Studies in Nationalism, 1983, Vol. 10 Issue 2, pp. 83–110
  64. ^ Giles MacDonogh, Frederick the Great: A Life in Deed and Letters (2001) p. 341
  65. ^ «Enlightenment ideals of rationalism and intellectual and religious freedom pervaded the American colonial religious landscape, and these values were instrumental in the American Revolution and the creation of a nation without an established religion». Enlightenment and Revolution, Pluralism Project, Harvard University.
  66. ^ Fremont-Barnes, Gregory (2007). Encyclopedia of the Age of Political Revolutions and New Ideologies, 1760–1815. Greenwood. p. 190. ISBN 9780313049514.
  67. ^ «Recognized in Europe as the author of the Declaration of Independence, Thomas Jefferson quickly became a focal point or lightning rod for revolutionaries in Europe and the Americas. As United States minister to France when revolutionary fervor was rising toward the storming of the Bastille in 1789, Jefferson became an ardent supporter of the French Revolution, even allowing his residence to be used as a meeting place for the rebels led by Lafayette». Thomas Jefferson. A Revolutionary World. Library of Congress.
  68. ^ Chartier, 8. See also Alexis de Tocqueville, L’Ancien Régime et la Révolution, 1850, Book Three, Chapter One.
  69. ^ Chartier, 13.
  70. ^ A Treatise on Toleration
  71. ^ Margaret C. Jacob, ed. The Enlightenment: Brief History with Documents, Boston: Bedford/St. Martin’s, 2001, Introduction, pp. 1–72.
  72. ^ Locke, John (1695). Reasonableness of Christianity. Vol. «Preface» The Reasonableness of Christianity, as delivered in the Scriptures.
  73. ^ R.B. Bernstein (2003). Thomas Jefferson. Oxford University Press. p. 179. ISBN 978-0-19-975844-9.
  74. ^ Ole Peter Grell; Porter, Roy (2000). Toleration in Enlightenment Europe. Cambridge University Press. pp. 1–68. ISBN 978-0-521-65196-7.
  75. ^ Baruch Spinoza, Theologico-Political Treatise, «Preface,» 1677, gutenberg.com
  76. ^ Mendelssohn, Moses (1783). «Jerusalem: Or on Religious Power and Judaism» (PDF).
  77. ^ Goetschel, Willi (2004). Spinoza’s Modernity: Mendelssohn, Lessing, and Heine. Univ of Wisconsin Press. p. 126. ISBN 978-0-299-19083-5.
  78. ^ Thomas Paine, Of the Religion of Deism Compared with the Christian Religion, 1804, Internet History Sourcebook
  79. ^ Ellen Judy Wilson; Peter Hanns Reill (2004). Encyclopedia Of The Enlightenment. Infobase Publishing. p. 148. ISBN 978-1-4381-1021-9.
  80. ^ Wilson and Reill (2004). Encyclopedia Of The Enlightenment. Infobase Publishing. p. 26. ISBN 978-1-4381-1021-9.
  81. ^ Pagden, Anthony (2013). The Enlightenment: And Why it Still Matters. Oxford University Press. p. 100. ISBN 978-0-19-966093-3.
  82. ^ Brown, Stuart (2003). British Philosophy and the Age of Enlightenment: Routledge History of Philosophy. Taylor & Francis. p. 256. ISBN 978-0-415-30877-9.
  83. ^ Bayle, Pierre (1741). A general dictionary: historical and critical: in which a new and accurate translation of that of the celebrated Mr. Bayle, with the corrections and observations printed in the late edition at Paris, is included; and interspersed with several thousand lives never before published. The whole containing the history of the most illustrious persons of all ages and nations particularly those of Great Britain and Ireland, distinguished by their rank, actions, learning and other accomplishments. With reflections on such passages of Bayle, as seem to favor scepticism and the Manichee system. p. 778.
  84. ^ ENR // AgencyND // University of Notre Dame (4 May 2003). «God, Locke and Equality: Christian Foundations of Locke’s Political Thought». Nd.edu.
  85. ^ Israel 2011, pp. 11.
  86. ^ Israel 2010, p. 19.
  87. ^ Israel 2010, pp. vii–viii.
  88. ^ Feldman, Noah (2005). Divided by God. Farrar, Straus, and Giroux, p. 29 («It took John Locke to translate the demand for liberty of conscience into a systematic argument for distinguishing the realm of government from the realm of religion.»)
  89. ^ Feldman, Noah (2005). Divided by God. Farrar, Straus, and Giroux, p. 29
  90. ^ Ferling, 2000, p. 158
  91. ^ Mayer, 1994 p. 76
  92. ^ Hayes, 2008, p. 10
  93. ^ Cogliano, 2003, p. 14
  94. ^ David N. Livingstone and Charles W.J. Withers, Geography and Enlightenment (1999)
  95. ^ a b A History of Modern Latin America: 1800 to the Present, Second Edition, by Teresa A. Meade
  96. ^ Peter Gay, ed. The Enlightenment: A comprehensive anthology (1973) p. 14
  97. ^ Roy Porter, «England» in Alan Charles Kors, ed., Encyclopedia of the Enlightenment (2003) 1:409–15.
  98. ^ Karen O’Brien, «English Enlightenment Histories, 1750–c.1815» in José Rabasa, ed. (2012). The Oxford History of Historical Writing: Volume 3: 1400–1800. Oxford, England: OUP. pp. 518–535. ISBN 978-0-19-921917-9.
  99. ^ Roy Porter, The creation of the modern world: the untold story of the British Enlightenment (2000), pp. 1–12, 482–484.
  100. ^ Eddy, Matthew Daniel (2022). Media and the Mind: Art, Science and Notebooks as Paper Machines, 1700-1830. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  101. ^ Towsey, Mark (2010). Reading the Scottish Enlightenment Books and Their Readers in Provincial Scotland, 1750-1820. Brill. ISBN 9789004193512.
  102. ^ A. Herman, How the Scots Invented the Modern World (Crown Publishing Group, 2001).
  103. ^ Harrison, Lawrence E. (2012). Jews, Confucians, and Protestants: Cultural Capital and the End of Multiculturalism. Rowman & Littlefield. p. 92. ISBN 978-1-4422-1964-9.
  104. ^ J. Repcheck, The Man Who Found Time: James Hutton and the Discovery of the Earth’s Antiquity (Basic Books, 2003), pp. 117–143.
  105. ^ Henry F. May, The Enlightenment in America (1978)
  106. ^ Michael Atiyah, «Benjamin Franklin and the Edinburgh Enlightenment,» Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society (Dec 2006) 150#4 pp. 591–606.
  107. ^ Jack Fruchtman, Jr., Atlantic Cousins: Benjamin Franklin and His Visionary Friends (2007)
  108. ^ Charles C. Mann, 1491 (2005)
  109. ^ Paul M. Spurlin, Montesquieu in America, 1760–1801 (1941)
  110. ^ «The Founding Fathers, Deism, and Christianity». Encyclopædia Britannica.
  111. ^ Charles W. Ingrao, «A Pre-Revolutionary Sonderweg.» German History 20#3 (2002), pp. 279–286.
  112. ^ Katrin Keller, «Saxony: Rétablissement and Enlightened Absolutism.» German History 20.3 (2002): 309–331.
  113. ^ «The German Enlightenment», German History (Dec 2017) 35#4 pp. 588–602, round table discussion of historiography.
  114. ^ Gagliardo, John G. (1991). Germany under the Old Regime, 1600–1790. pp. 217–234, 375–395.
  115. ^ Richter, Simon J., ed. (2005), The Literature of Weimar Classicism
  116. ^ Owens, Samantha; Reul, Barbara M.; Stockigt, Janice B., eds. (2011). Music at German Courts, 1715–1760: Changing Artistic Priorities.
  117. ^ Kuehn, Manfred (2001). Kant: A Biography.
  118. ^ Van Dulmen, Richard; Williams, Anthony, eds. (1992). The Society of the Enlightenment: The Rise of the Middle Class and Enlightenment Culture in Germany.
  119. ^ Thomas P. Saine, The Problem of Being Modern, or the German Pursuit of Enlightenment from Leibniz to the French Revolution (1997)
  120. ^ Michael J. Sauter, «The Enlightenment on trial: state service and social discipline in eighteenth-century Germany’s public sphere.» Modern Intellectual History 5.2 (2008): 195–223.
  121. ^ Mori, Massimo (1 February 2015). Storia della filosofia moderna (in Italian). Gius.Laterza & Figli Spa. ISBN 978-88-581-1845-0.
  122. ^ D’Onofrio, Federico (2015). On the caoncept of ‘felicitas publica’ in Eighteenth-Century political economy, in History of economic thought.
  123. ^ Niccolò Guasti, «Antonio Genovesi’s Diceosina: Source of the Neapolitan Enlightenment.» History of European ideas 32.4 (2006): 385–405.
  124. ^ Pier Luigi Porta, «Lombard enlightenment and classical political economy.» The European Journal of the History of Economic Thought 18.4 (2011): 521–50.
  125. ^ Franco Venturi, Italy and the Enlightenment: studies in a cosmopolitan century (1972) online
  126. ^ Anna Maria Rao, «Enlightenment and reform: an overview of culture and politics in Enlightenment Italy.» Journal of Modern Italian Studies 10.2 (2005): 142–67.
  127. ^ Aldridge, Alfred Owen. The Ibero-American Enlightenment. Urbana: University of Illinois Press 1971.
  128. ^ De Vos, Paula S. «Research, Development, and Empire: State Support of Science in Spain and Spanish America, Sixteenth to Eighteenth Centuries,» Colonial Latin America Review 15, no. 1 (June 2006) 55–79.
  129. ^ Bleichmar, Daniela. Visible Empire: Botanical Expeditions & Visual Culture in the Hispanic Enlightenment. Chicago: University of Chicago Press 2012.
  130. ^ Brading, D. A. The First America: The Spanish Monarchy, Creole Patriots, and the Liberal State, 1492–1867 Chapter 23, «Scientific Traveller». New York: Cambridge University Press 1991 ISBN 0-521-39130-X
  131. ^ Thiessen, Heather. «Spain: Constitution of 1812.» Encyclopedia of Latin American History and Culture, vol. 5, p. 165. New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons 1996.
  132. ^ Cohen, Thomas M. (15 November 2018). «Six Sermons, written by António Vieira». Journal of Jesuit Studies. 5 (4): 692–695. doi:10.1163/22141332-00504010-11. ISSN 2214-1324.
  133. ^ Elise Kimerling Wirtschafter, «Thoughts on the Enlightenment and Enlightenment in Russia», Modern Russian History & Historiography, 2009, Vol. 2 Issue 2, pp. 1–26
  134. ^ Israel 2011, pp. 609–32.
  135. ^ Colum Leckey, «What is Prosveshchenie? Nikolai Novikov’s Historical Dictionary of Russian Writers Revisited.» Russian History 37.4 (2010): 360–77.
  136. ^ Maciej Janowski, «Warsaw and Its Intelligentsia: Urban Space and Social Change, 1750–1831.» Acta Poloniae Historica 100 (2009): 57–77. ISSN 0001-6829
  137. ^ Richard Butterwick, «What is Enlightenment (oświecenie)? Some Polish Answers, 1765–1820.» Central Europe 3.1 (2005): 19–37. online[dead link]
  138. ^ Jerzy Snopek, «The Polish Literature of the Enlightenment.» Archived 5 October 2011 at the Wayback Machine (PDF 122 KB) Poland.pl. Retrieved 7 October 2011.
  139. ^ Ronald P. Toby, State and Diplomacy in Early Modern Japan: Asia in the Development of the Tokugawa Bakufu, Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press, (1984) 1991.
  140. ^ Keith Thomas, «The Great Fight Over the Enlightenment,» The New York Review April 3, 2014
  141. ^ a b Thomas, 2014
  142. ^
    Ritchie Robertson, «The Enlightenment: The Pursuit of Happiness, 1680–1790.» (2020) ch. 1.
  143. ^ Oxford English Dictionary, 3rd Edn (revised)
  144. ^ Lough, John (1985). «Reflections on Enlightenment and Lumieres». Journal for Eighteenth-Century Studies. 8#1: 1–15. doi:10.1111/j.1754-0208.1985.tb00093.x.
  145. ^ Jean le Rond d’Alembert, Discours préliminaire de l’Encyclopédie
  146. ^ Outram, 1. The past tense is used deliberately as whether man would educate himself or be educated by certain exemplary figures was a common issue at the time. D’Alembert’s introduction to l’Encyclopédie, for example, along with Immanuel Kant’s essay response (the «independent thinkers»), both support the later model.
  147. ^ Immanuel Kant, «What is Enlightenment?», 1.
  148. ^ Porter 2001, p. 1
  149. ^ Ernst Cassirer, The Philosophy of the Enlightenment, (1951), p. vi
  150. ^ Porter 2001, p. 70
  151. ^ a b Russell, Bertrand. A History of Western Philosophy. pp. 492–494
  152. ^ Israel 2010, pp. 49–50.
  153. ^ Israel 2006, pp. v–viii.
  154. ^ Israel 2001, pp. 3.
  155. ^ Martin Heidegger [1938] (2002) The Age of the World Picture quotation:

    For up to Descartes … a particular sub-iectum … lies at the foundation of its own fixed qualities and changing circumstances. The superiority of a sub-iectum … arises out of the claim of man to a … self-supported, unshakeable foundation of truth, in the sense of certainty. Why and how does this claim acquire its decisive authority? The claim originates in that emancipation of man in which he frees himself from obligation to Christian revelational truth and Church doctrine to a legislating for himself that takes its stand upon itself.

  156. ^ Ingraffia, Brian D. (1995) Postmodern theory and biblical theology: vanquishing God’s shadow p. 126
  157. ^ Norman K. Swazo (2002) Crisis theory and world order: Heideggerian reflections pp. 97–99
  158. ^ Shank, J. B. The Newton Wars and the Beginning of the French Enlightenment (2008), «Introduction»[page needed]
  159. ^ «PHYS 200 – Lecture 3 – Newton’s Laws of Motion – Open Yale Courses». oyc.yale.edu.
  160. ^ Anderson, M. S. Historians and eighteenth-century Europe, 1715–1789 (Oxford UP, 1979); Jean de Viguerie, Histoire et dictionnaire du temps des Lumières (1715–1789) (Paris: Robert Laffont, 1995).
  161. ^ Frost, Martin (2008), The age of Enlightenment, archived from the original on 10 October 2007, retrieved 18 January 2008
  162. ^ Theodor W. Adorno; Horkheimer, Max (1947). «The Concept of Enlightenment». In G.S. Noerr (ed.). Dialectic of Enlightenment: Philosophical Fragments. Translated by E. Jephcott. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press. p. 3. ISBN 978-1-85984-154-9.
  163. ^ Josephson-Storm, Jason (2017). The Myth of Disenchantment: Magic, Modernity, and the Birth of the Human Sciences. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. pp. 58–61. ISBN 978-0-226-40336-6.
  164. ^ Josephson-Storm, Jason (2017). The Myth of Disenchantment: Magic, Modernity, and the Birth of the Human Sciences. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. pp. 61–62. ISBN 978-0-226-40336-6.
  165. ^ Outram, 6. See also, A. Owen Alridge (ed.), The Ibero-American Enlightenment (1971)., Franco Venturi, The End of the Old Regime in Europe 1768–1776: The First Crisis.
  166. ^ James Van Horn Melton, The Rise of the Public in Enlightenment Europe (2001), p. 4.
  167. ^ Jürgen Habermas, The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere, (1989), pp. 36, 37.
  168. ^ Melton, 8.
  169. ^ Nicolaas A. Rupke (2008). «Alexander Von Humboldt: A Metabiography«. University of Chicago Press. p. 138 ISBN 0-226-73149-9
  170. ^ Melton, 4, 5. Habermas, 14–26.
  171. ^ Daniel Brewer, ed. (2014). The Cambridge Companion to the French Enlightenment. Cambridge UP. pp. 91ff. ISBN 978-1-316-19432-4.
  172. ^ Outram, Dorinda. The Enlightenment (2nd ed.). Cambridge University Press, 2005, p. 12.
  173. ^ Outram 2005, p. 13.
  174. ^ Chartier, 27.
  175. ^ Mona Ozouf, «‘Public Opinion’ at the End of the Old Regime»
  176. ^ David Beard and Kenneth Gloag, Musicology, The Key Concepts (New York: Routledge, 2005), 58.
  177. ^ J. Peter Burkholder, Donald J. Grout, and Claude V. Palisca, A History of Western Music, Seventh Edition, (New York: W.W. Norton & Company, Inc., 2006), 475.
  178. ^ a b Beard and Gloag, Musicology, 59.
  179. ^ a b Beard and Gloag, Musicology, 60.
  180. ^ a b c Burkholder, Grout, and Palisca, A History of Western Music, 475.
  181. ^ a b c Outram, 21.
  182. ^ Chartier, 26.
  183. ^ Chartier, 26, 26. Kant, «What is Enlightenment?»
  184. ^ Outram, 23.
  185. ^ Goodman, 3.
  186. ^ Dena Goodman, The Republic of Letters: A Cultural History of the French Enlightenment (1994), 53.
  187. ^ Carla Hesse, The Other Enlightenment: How French Women Became Modern (2001), 42.
  188. ^ Crébillon fils, quoted from Darnton, The Literary Underground, 17.
  189. ^ Darnton, The Literary Underground, 19, 20.
  190. ^ Darnton, «The Literary Underground», 21, 23.
  191. ^ Darnton, The Literary Underground, 29
  192. ^ Outram, 22.
  193. ^ Darnton, The Literary Underground, 35–40.
  194. ^ Outram, 17, 20.
  195. ^ Darnton, «The Literary Underground», 16.
  196. ^ from Outram, 19. See Rolf Engelsing, «Die Perioden der Lesergeschichte in der Neuzeit. Das statische Ausmass und die soziokulturelle Bedeutung der Lektüre», Archiv für Geschichte des Buchwesens, 10 (1969), cols. 944–1002 and Der Bürger als Leser: Lesergeschichte in Deutschland, 1500–1800 (Stuttgart, 1974).
  197. ^ «history of publishing :: Developments in the 18th century». Encyclopædia Britannica.
  198. ^ Outram, 27–29
  199. ^ Erin Mackie, The Commerce of Everyday Life: Selections from The Tatler and The Spectator (Boston: Bedford/St. Martin’s, 1998), 16.
  200. ^ See Mackie, Darnton, An Early Information Society
  201. ^ In particular, see Chapter 6, «Reading, Writing and Publishing»
  202. ^ See Darnton, The Literary Underground, 184.
  203. ^ a b Darnton, The Literary Underground, 135–47.
  204. ^ Darnton, The Business of Enlightenment, 12, 13. For a more detailed description of French censorship laws, see Darnton, The Literary Underground
  205. ^ Eddy, Matthew Daniel (2008). The Language of Mineralogy: John Walker, Chemistry and the Edinburgh Medical School, 1750–1800. Ashgate.
  206. ^ Emma Spary, «The ‘Nature’ of Enlightenment» in The Sciences in Enlightened Europe, William Clark, Jan Golinski, and Steven Schaffer, eds. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1999), 281–82.
  207. ^ Spary, 289–93.
  208. ^ See Thomas Laqueur, Making sex: body and gender from the Greeks to Freud (1990).
  209. ^ Israel 2001, pp. 143–44.
  210. ^ Israel 2001, pp. 142.
  211. ^ Israel 2001, pp. 150–51.
  212. ^ a b Headrick, (2000), p. 144.
  213. ^ a b Headrick, (2000), p. 172.
  214. ^ Porter, (2003), pp. 249–250.
  215. ^ Headrick, (2000), p. 168.
  216. ^ Headrick, (2000), pp. 150–152.
  217. ^ Headrick, (2000), p. 153.
  218. ^ d’Alembert, p. 4.
  219. ^ Darnton, (1979), p. 7.
  220. ^ Darnton, (1979), p. 37.
  221. ^ Darnton, (1979), p. 6.
  222. ^ Jacob, (1988), p. 191; Melton, (2001), pp. 82–83
  223. ^ Headrick, (2000), p. 15
  224. ^ Headrick, (2000), p. 19.
  225. ^ Phillips, (1991), pp. 85, 90
  226. ^ Phillips, (1991), p. 90.
  227. ^ Porter, (2003), p. 300.
  228. ^ Porter, (2003), p. 101.
  229. ^ Phillips, (1991), p. 92.
  230. ^ Phillips, (1991), p. 107.
  231. ^ Eddy, Matthew Daniel (2013). «The Shape of Knowledge: Children and the Visual Culture of Literacy and Numeracy». Science in Context. 26 (2): 215–245. doi:10.1017/s0269889713000045. S2CID 147123263.
  232. ^ Hotson, Howard (2007). Commonplace Learning: Ramism and Its German Ramifications 1543–1630. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  233. ^ Eddy, Matthew Daniel (2008). The Language of Mineralogy: John Walker, Chemistry and the Edinburgh Medical School, 1750–1800. Aldershot: Ashgate.
  234. ^ Elizabeth Williams, A Cultural History of Medical Vitalism in Enlightenment Montpellier (2003) p. 50
  235. ^ Peter Barrett (2004), Science and Theology Since Copernicus: The Search for Understanding, p. 14, Continuum International Publishing Group, ISBN 0-567-08969-X
  236. ^ Daniel Roche, France in the Enlightenment, (1998), 420.
  237. ^ Roche, 515–16.
  238. ^ Caradonna JL. Annales, «Prendre part au siècle des Lumières: Le concours académique et la culture intellectuelle au XVIIIe siècle»
  239. ^ Jeremy L. Caradonna, «Prendre part au siècle des Lumières: Le concours académique et la culture intellectuelle au XVIIIe siècle», Annales. Histoire, Sciences sociales, vol. 64 (mai-juin 2009), n. 3, 633–62.
  240. ^ Caradonna, 634–36.
  241. ^ Caradonna, 653–54.
  242. ^ «Royal Charters». royalsociety.org.
  243. ^ Steven Shapin, A Social History of Truth: Civility and Science in Seventeenth-Century England, Chicago; London: University of Chicago Press, 1994.
  244. ^ Steven Shapin and Simon Schaffer, Leviathan and the Air-Pump: Hobbes, Boyle, and the Experimental Life (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1985), 5, 56, 57. This same desire for multiple witnesses led to attempts at replication in other locations and a complex iconography and literary technology developed to provide visual and written proof of experimentation. See pp. 59–65.
  245. ^ Shapin and Schaffer, 58, 59.
  246. ^ Klein, Lawrence E. (1 January 1996). «Coffeehouse Civility, 1660–1714: An Aspect of Post-Courtly Culture in England». Huntington Library Quarterly. 59 (1): 31–51. doi:10.2307/3817904. JSTOR 3817904.
  247. ^ Klein, 35.
  248. ^ Cowan, 90, 91.
  249. ^ Colin Jones, Paris: Biography of a City (New York: Viking, 2004), 188, 189.
  250. ^ Darnton, Robert (2000). «An Early Information Society: News and the Media in Eighteenth-Century Paris». The American Historical Review. 105#1 (1): 1–35. doi:10.2307/2652433. JSTOR 2652433.
  251. ^ Donna T. Andrew, «Popular Culture and Public Debate: London 1780», This Historical Journal, Vol. 39, No. 2. (June 1996), pp. 405–423.
  252. ^ Andrew, 406. Andrew gives the name as «William Henley», which must be a lapse of writing.
  253. ^ Andrew, 408.
  254. ^ Andrew, 406–08, 411.
  255. ^ a b Israel 2001, p. 4.
  256. ^ Andrew, 412–15.
  257. ^ Andrew, 422.
  258. ^ Crow, Matthew; Jacob, Margaret (2014). «Freemasonry and the Enlightenment». In Bodgan, Henrik; Snoek, Jan A. M. (eds.). Handbook of Freemasonry. Brill Handbooks on Contemporary Religion. Vol. 8. Leiden: Brill Publishers. pp. 100–116. doi:10.1163/9789004273122_008. ISBN 978-90-04-21833-8. ISSN 1874-6691.
  259. ^ Maynard Mack, Alexander Pope: A Life, Yale University Press, 1985 p. 437–440. Pope, a Catholic, was a Freemason in 1730, eight years before membership was prohibited by the Catholic Church (1738). Pope’s name is on the membership list of the Goat Tavern Lodge (p. 439). Pope’s name appears on a 1723 list and a 1730 list.
  260. ^ J.A. Leo Lemay (2013). The Life of Benjamin Franklin, Volume 2: Printer and Publisher, 1730–1747. University of Pennsylvania Press. pp. 83–92. ISBN 978-0-8122-0929-7.
  261. ^ Bullock, Steven C. (1996). «Initiating the Enlightenment?: Recent Scholarship on European Freemasonry». Eighteenth-Century Life. 20 (1): 81.
  262. ^ Norman Davies, Europe: A History (1996) pp. 634–635
  263. ^ Margaret C. Jacob’s seminal work on Enlightenment freemasonry, Margaret C. Jacob, Living the Enlightenment: Free masonry and Politics in Eighteenth-Century Europe (Oxford University Press, 1991) p. 49.
  264. ^ Margaret C. Jacob, «Polite worlds of Enlightenment,» in Martin Fitzpatrick and Peter Jones, eds. The Enlightenment World (Routledge, 2004) pp. 272–287.
  265. ^ Roche, 436.
  266. ^ Fitzpatrick and Jones, eds. The Enlightenment World p. 281
  267. ^ Jacob, pp. 20, 73, 89.
  268. ^ Jacob, 145–47.
  269. ^ Reinhart Koselleck, Critique and Crisis, p. 62, (The MIT Press, 1988)
  270. ^ Thomas Munck, 1994, p. 70.
  271. ^ Diderot, Denis (1769). «D’Alembert’s Dream» (PDF). Archived from the original (PDF) on 29 November 2014. Retrieved 17 November 2014.
  272. ^ Margaret C. Jacob, Living the Enlightenment: Freemasonry and politics in eighteenth-century Europe (Oxford University Press, 1991.)
  273. ^ Roche, 437.
  274. ^ Jacob, 139. See also Janet M. Burke, «Freemasonry, Friendship and Noblewomen: The Role of the Secret Society in Bringing Enlightenment Thought to Pre-Revolutionary Women Elites», History of European Ideas 10 no. 3 (1989): 283–94.
  275. ^ Davies, Europe: A History (1996) pp. 634–635
  276. ^ Richard Weisberger et al., eds., Freemasonry on both sides of the Atlantic: essays concerning the craft in the British Isles, Europe, the United States, and Mexico (2002)
  277. ^ Robert R. Palmer, The Age of the Democratic Revolution: The Struggle (1970) p. 53
  278. ^ Neil L. York, «Freemasons and the American Revolution», The Historian Volume: 55. Issue: 2. 1993, pp. 315+.
  279. ^ Janson, H. W.; Janson, Anthony (2003). A Basic History of Art. New York: Harry N. Abrams, Inc. pp. 458–474.

Sources[edit]

  • Andrew, Donna T. «Popular Culture and Public Debate: London 1780». The Historical Journal, Vol. 39, No. 2. (June 1996), pp. 405–423. in JSTOR
  • Burns, William. Science in the Enlightenment: An Encyclopædia (2003)
  • Cowan, Brian, The Social Life of Coffee: The Emergence of the British Coffeehouse. New Haven: Yale University Press, 2005
  • Darnton, Robert. The Literary Underground of the Old Regime. (1982).
  • Israel, Jonathan I. (2001). Radical Enlightenment; Philosophy and the Making of Modernity 1650–1750. Oxford University Press.
  • Israel, Jonathan I. (2006). Enlightenment Contested. Oxford University Press.
  • Israel, Jonathan I. (2010). A Revolution of the Mind: Radical Enlightenment and the Intellectual Origins of Modern Democracy. Princeton.
  • Israel, Jonathan I. (2011). Democratic Enlightenment: Philosophy, Revolution, and Human Rights 1750–1790. Oxford University Press.
  • Melton, James Van Horn. The Rise of the Public in Enlightenment Europe. (2001).
  • Petitfils, Jean-Christian (2005). Louis XVI. Perrin. ISBN 978-2-7441-9130-5.
  • Robertson, Ritchie. The Enlightenment: The Pursuit of Happiness, 1680–1790. London: Allen Lane, 2020; New York: HarperCollins, 2021
  • Ferrone, Vincenzo (2017). The Enlightenment: History of an Idea. Princeton University Press.
  • Pinker, Steven (2018). Enlightenment Now: The Case for Reason, Science, Humanism, and Progress. Penguin Books.
  • Roche, Daniel. France in the Enlightenment. (1998).

Further reading[edit]

Reference and surveys[edit]

  • Becker, Carl L. The Heavenly City of the Eighteenth-Century Philosophers. (1932), a famous short classic
  • Chisick, Harvey. Historical Dictionary of the Enlightenment (2005)
  • Delon, Michel. Encyclopædia of the Enlightenment (2001) 1480 pp.
  • Dupré, Louis. The Enlightenment and the Intellectual Foundations of Modern Culture (2004)
  • Gay, Peter. The Enlightenment: The Rise of Modern Paganism (1966, 2nd ed. 1995), 592 pp. excerpt and text search vol 1.
  • Gay, Peter. The Enlightenment: The Science of Freedom (1969, 2nd ed. 1995), a highly influential study excerpt and text search vol 2;
  • Greensides F., Hyland P., Gomez O. (ed.). The Enlightenment (2002)
  • Fitzpatrick, Martin et al., eds. The Enlightenment World (2004). 714 pp. 39 essays by scholars
  • Hampson, Norman. The Enlightenment (1981) online
  • Hazard, Paul. European Thought in the 18th Century: From Montesquieu to Lessing (1965)
  • Hesmyr, Atle. From Enlightenment to Romanticism in 18th Century Europe (2018)
  • Himmelfarb, Gertrude. The Roads to Modernity: The British, French, and American Enlightenments (2004) excerpt and text search
  • Jacob, Margaret. Enlightenment: A Brief History with Documents 2000
  • Kors, Alan Charles. Encyclopædia of the Enlightenment (4 vol. 1990; 2nd ed. 2003), 1984 pp. excerpt and text search
  • Lehner, Ulrich L. The Catholic Enlightenment (2016)
  • Lehner, Ulrich L. Women, Catholicism and Enlightenment (2017)
  • Munck, Thomas. Enlightenment: A Comparative Social History, 1721–1794 (1994)
  • Outram, Dorinda. The Enlightenment (1995) 157 pp. excerpt and text search; also online
  • Outram, Dorinda. Panorama of the Enlightenment (2006), emphasis on Germany; heavily illustrated
  • Porter, Roy (2001), The Enlightenment (2nd ed.), ISBN 978-0-333-94505-6
  • Reill, Peter Hanns, and Wilson, Ellen Judy. Encyclopædia of the Enlightenment. (2nd ed. 2004). 670 pp.
  • Robertson, Ritchie. The Enlightenment: The Pursuit of Happiness, 1680-1790. (2021).
  • Sarmant, Thierry (2012). Histoire de Paris: Politique, urbanisme, civilisation. Editions Jean-Paul Gisserot. ISBN 978-2-7558-0330-3.
  • Warman, Caroline; et al. (2016), Warman, Caroline (ed.), Tolerance: The Beacon of the Enlightenment, Open Book Publishers, doi:10.11647/OBP.0088, ISBN 978-1-78374-203-5
  • Yolton, John W. et al. The Blackwell Companion to the Enlightenment. (1992). 581 pp.

Specialty studies[edit]

  • Aldridge, A. Owen (ed.). The Ibero-American Enlightenment (1971).
  • Artz, Frederick B. The Enlightenment in France (1998) online
  • Brewer, Daniel. The Enlightenment Past: Reconstructing 18th-Century French Thought (2008)
  • Broadie, Alexander. The Scottish Enlightenment: The Historical Age of the Historical Nation (2007)
  • Broadie, Alexander. The Cambridge Companion to the Scottish Enlightenment (2003) excerpt and text search
  • Bronner, Stephen (1995). «The Great Divide: The Enlightenment and its Critics». New Politics. 5: 65–86.
  • Brown, Stuart, ed. British Philosophy in the Age of Enlightenment (2002)
  • Buchan, James. Crowded with Genius: The Scottish Enlightenment: Edinburgh’s Moment of the Mind (2004) excerpt and text search
  • Burrows, Simon. (2013) «In Search of Enlightenment: From Mapping Books to Cultural History.» Journal for Early Modern Cultural Studies 13, no. 4: 3–28.
  • Campbell, R.S. and Skinner, A.S., (eds.) The Origins and Nature of the Scottish Enlightenment, Edinburgh, 1982
  • Cassirer, Ernst. The Philosophy of the Enlightenment. 1955. a highly influential study by a neoKantian philosopher excerpt and text search
  • Chartier, Roger. The Cultural Origins of the French Revolution. Translated by Lydia G. Cochrane. Duke University Press, 1991.
  • Europe in the age of enlightenment and revolution. New York: The Metropolitan Museum of Art. 1989. ISBN 978-0-87099-451-7.
  • Edelstein, Dan. The Enlightenment: A Genealogy (University of Chicago Press; 2010) 209 pp.
  • Golinski, Jan (2011). «Science in the Enlightenment, Revisited». History of Science. 49 (2): 217–231. Bibcode:2011HisSc..49..217G. doi:10.1177/007327531104900204. S2CID 142886527.
  • Goodman, Dena. The Republic of Letters: A Cultural History of the French Enlightenment. (1994).
  • Hesse, Carla. The Other Enlightenment: How French Women Became Modern. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2001.
  • Hankins, Thomas L. Science and the Enlightenment (1985).
  • May, Henry F. The Enlightenment in America. 1976. 419 pp.
  • Porter, Roy. The Creation of the Modern World: The Untold Story of the British Enlightenment. 2000. 608 pp. excerpt and text search
  • Redkop, Benjamin. The Enlightenment and Community, 1999
  • Reid-Maroney, Nina. Philadelphia’s Enlightenment, 1740–1800: Kingdom of Christ, Empire of Reason. 2001. 199 pp.
  • Schmidt, James (2003). «Inventing the Enlightenment: Anti-Jacobins, British Hegelians, and the ‘Oxford English Dictionary’«. Journal of the History of Ideas. 64 (3): 421–443. doi:10.2307/3654234. JSTOR 3654234.
  • Sorkin, David. The Religious Enlightenment: Protestants, Jews, and Catholics from London to Vienna (2008)
  • Staloff, Darren. Hamilton, Adams, Jefferson: The Politics of Enlightenment and the American Founding. 2005. 419 pp. excerpt and text search
  • Suitner, Riccarda. The Dialogues of the Dead of the Early German Enlightenment (Leiden-Boston: Brill, 2022)
  • Till, Nicholas. Mozart and the Enlightenment: Truth, Virtue, and Beauty in Mozart’s Operas. 1993. 384 pp.
  • Tunstall, Kate E. Blindness and Enlightenment. An Essay. With a new translation of Diderot’s Letter on the Blind (Continuum, 2011)
  • Venturi, Franco. Utopia and Reform in the Enlightenment. George Macaulay Trevelyan Lecture, (1971)
  • Venturi, Franco. Italy and the Enlightenment: studies in a cosmopolitan century (1972) online
  • Wills, Garry. Cincinnatus: George Washington and the Enlightenment (1984) online
  • Winterer, Caroline. American Enlightenments: Pursuing Happiness in the Age of Reason (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2016)
  • Navarro i Soriano, Ferran (2019). Harca, harca, harca! Músiques per a la recreació històrica de la Guerra de Successió (1794–1715). Editorial DENES. ISBN 978-84-16473-45-8.

Primary sources[edit]

  • Broadie, Alexander, ed. The Scottish Enlightenment: An Anthology (2001) excerpt and text search
  • Diderot, Denis. Rameau’s Nephew and other Works (2008) excerpt and text search.
  • Diderot, Denis. «Letter on the Blind» in Tunstall, Kate E. Blindness and Enlightenment. An Essay. With a new translation of Diderot’s Letter on the Blind (Continuum, 2011)
  • Diderot, Denis. The Encyclopédie of Diderot and D’Alembert: Selected Articles (1969) excerpt and text search Collaborative Translation Project of the University of Michigan
  • Gay, Peter, ed. (1973). The Enlightenment: A Comprehensive Anthology. ISBN 0671217070.
  • Gomez, Olga, et al. eds. The Enlightenment: A Sourcebook and Reader (2001) excerpt and text search
  • Kramnick, Issac, ed. The Portable Enlightenment Reader (1995) excerpt and text search
  • Manuel, Frank Edward, ed. The Enlightenment (1965) online, excerpts
  • Schmidt, James, ed. What is Enlightenment?: Eighteenth-Century Answers and Twentieth-Century Questions (1996) excerpt and text search

External links[edit]

  • Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). «Enlightenment». Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Age of Enlightenment at PhilPapers
  • Age of Enlightenment at the Indiana Philosophy Ontology Project
  • Collection: Art of the Enlightenment Era from the University of Michigan Museum of Art

Просвеще́ние, термин, используемый для обозначения эпохи в истории культуры, общественной и философской мысли стран Европы и Америки. Начало эпохи Просвещения обычно относят ко 2-й половине 17 в., в качестве верхней границы указывают начало Французской революции 18 в., хотя в некоторых странах продлевают до начала 19 в. В историографии на протяжении 19 и большей части 20 вв. Просвещение рассматривалось как идеологическая подготовка революции во Франции. К концу 20 – началу 21 вв. подобная трактовка, заметно обеднявшая значение достижений эпохи и выдвигавшая на передний план только французское Просвещение, сменилась более широким подходом. В соответствии с ним Просвещение – феномен культуры, обладающий самостоятельной ценностью вне зависимости от каких-либо последующих событий. Кроме того, Просвещение более не рассматривается лишь как комплекс идей. Обращается внимание также на произошедшие в 18 в. изменения в культуре повседневности.

Идеология Просвещения сформировалась под воздействием достижений культуры Возрождения и научной революции 17 в. (научная деятельность Ф. Бэкона, Р. Декарта, Г. В. Лейбница, И. Ньютона, Б. Спинозы и др.), знаменовавшей важный этап в преодолении зависимости науки от религии, бурный рост точных и естественных наук (физики, математики, механики, астрономии). Развитие этих наук породило веру в безграничные способности разума к познанию, привело к широкому распространению рационалистических идей. Многие просветители значительное время посвящали занятиям естественными науками (Ж. Л. Д’Аламбер, И. В. Гёте, А. Л. де Лавуазье, Б. Франклин и др.). Рост эмпирической информации привёл к появлению обобщающих трудов по отдельным областям знания (например, «Система природы» К. Линнея) и универсальных справочных изданий («Циклопедия» Э. Чемберса, «Энциклопедия» Д. Дидро и Ж. Л. Д’Аламбера, «Британская энциклопедия» и др.). Стремление преобразовать социальную действительность на рациональных началах обусловило отказ от всего, что не могло быть признано разумным, следовательно причислялось к предрассудкам и суевериям. Утверждая всемогущество разума, просветители придали новый импульс идее прогресса, который можно наблюдать не только в научной, но и в общественной сфере. Познание, способное изменить судьбу человека, стало целью, к которой должно стремиться общество. Другая общая черта мировоззрения просветителей – стремление к секуляризации общественной жизни и призыв к веротерпимости. Однако, несмотря на разочарование в религии как в единственном источнике истины, не все просветители пришли к полному её отрицанию: большинство из них призывали лишь ограничить роль религии в жизни общества и осуждали религиозный фанатизм. Традиционным религиям просветители противопоставили т. н. религию разума, которой стал деизм, мысливший Бога как безличную первопричину мира, сообщившего ему неизменные законы природы и не вмешивающегося в их действия. По их мнению, человек обладает врождённой естественной моралью, а все пороки являются результатом заблуждений и предрассудков. Следствием этого стало повышенное внимание просветителей к вопросам образования и воспитания как главному средству улучшения общества: идеи решающего влияния среды на воспитание, природного равенства способностей, необходимости соответствия воспитания человеческой природе, естественным склонностям ребёнка, требование реального образования и др. (например, Дж. Локк, К. А. Гельвеций, Дидро, Ж.-Ж. Руссо, И. Г. Песталоцци).

Критика просветителей была направлена и против абсолютистского государства с его системой сословных привилегий. Эпоха Просвещения стала временем окончательного формирования современных представлений о светском государстве, основанном на взаимных обязательствах между людьми (теория общественного договора, предложенная Г. Гроцием и развитая Т. Гоббсом, Локком, Руссо). Теория естественного права, исходившая из представления о прирождённом равенстве людей, идеологически обосновала требования демократических свобод. В этот период зародились многие черты современной политической системы: понятие гражданских прав и свобод (включая свободу совести), принцип разделения властей (Локк, Ш. Л. Монтескьё) и др. Многие просветители видели в просвещённом монархе человека, способного осуществить необходимые преобразования, направленные на ликвидацию провинциальной обособленности и установление политического единства нации, что привело к формированию т. н. просвещённого абсолютизма. Другая часть просветителей отстаивала идеи народного суверенитета и демократической республики (Руссо).

В области экономики большинство просветителей придерживались принципа соревнования частных интересов, требовали введения свободы торговли, правовых гарантий частной собственности (физиократы, А. Смит и др.). Для просветительских взглядов на историю наиболее характерна идея об объективных закономерностях и общих стадиях развития человечества, определяемых прогрессом, который рассматривался как поступательное развитие культуры, торговли, промышленности, техники (И. Г. Гердер, Н. Кондорсе). В. Мирабо ввёл в оборот термин «цивилизация», которым стали обозначать передовое состояние общества и культуры, а также процесс, ведущий к такому состоянию (А. Фергюсон). Просветители отрицательно относились к эпохе Средневековья, в которой видели период невежества, фанатизма, религиозных предрассудков, тирании, и преклонялись перед Античностью.

Новые идеи, появившиеся в эпоху Просвещения, быстро распространялись в обществе и оказывали большое влияние на его жизнь благодаря кардинальным изменениям, произошедшим в культуре повседневности. В первую очередь они заключались в переменах в практике чтения. На протяжении 18 в. значительно возросла грамотность населения (во Франции, например, до 47 % среди мужчин и до 27 % среди женщин), быстро росло и количество печатной продукции, бо́льшую часть которой занимала светская и художественная литература. Изменился формат книг – их можно было читать не только за столом, но и во время прогулки, в дороге и т. д. К чтению приобщились новые социальные слои – ремесленники, слуги, крестьяне. Во 2-й половине 18 в. широко распространились общественные читальни, где можно было получить газеты и журналы, подписка на которые стоила дорого, воспользоваться справочниками, словарями, альманахами, познакомиться со злободневными новинками. Появилась возможность брать книги на время на дом. Кардинально изменился качественный состав печатной продукции – резко возросла доля периодики. Если в первое десятилетие 18 в. выходило 40 французских и 64 немецких периодических изданий, то в 1770-х гг. соответственно 188 и 718, в следующее десятилетие 1225 и 2277.

Развитие книгопечатания и периодики стало залогом широкого распространения идей, благодаря чему сложилась новая социальная реальность – общественное мнение, т. е. коллективные суждения, формирующиеся вне сферы, подконтрольной правительству, и оказывающие влияние на процесс принятия политических решений. Новые идеи стали предметом дискуссии. Появлялось большое количество мест, где люди могли обмениваться мнениями о различных аспектах общественной и духовной жизни, – академии, читательские клубы, интеллектуальные кружки, литературные салоны, кафе и т. д. Наиболее распространённой формой интеллектуальных сообществ были масонские ложи. Члены этих сообществ поддерживали постоянные контакты между собой, вели регулярную переписку с членами аналогичных объединений в других городах и странах, что позволяло новым идеям более активно распространяться в странах Европы и Америки.

Значительные изменения претерпела и система образования. Совершенствовались учебные заведения – коллегии, пансионы. Во 2-й половине 18 в. началось формирование государственной системы народных школ, причём прежде всего в многонациональных государствах (Пруссия, империя Габсбургов, Россия). Аристократия предпочитала давать своим детям домашнее образование, для представителей обедневшей знати создавались специальные, чаще всего военные, учебные заведения.

Различия социально-экономических условий и национальных традиций обусловили специфику Просвещения в разных странах.

Просвещение в Англии и Шотландии

Влияние на Просвещение в Англии и Шотландии оказали изменения в области социально-экономического развития, революции 17 в. и социокультурные сдвиги 17–18 вв. Большое значение имело раннее развитие парламентаризма с присущими ему правовыми способами политической борьбы и разрешения общественных противоречий, а также относительно высокий уровень культурного и политического просвещения широких слоёв населения. На характер английского Просвещения повлияли также его взаимоотношения с религией и Церковью. Видные деятели Просвещения придерживались догматов христианства, чему способствовала позиция Англиканской церкви, не противопоставлявшей себя Просвещению и отвечавшей его стремлению к веротерпимости, что позволяло сохранять известное равновесие между традиционными ценностями, хранителем которых выступала Церковь, и новаторскими, которые несло Просвещение. Английские просветители редко критиковали Церковь и христианство, исключением являлся Дж. Толанд.

Политическую программу английского Просвещения сформулировал в основных чертах Дж. Локк. «Славная революция» и принятый в 1689 г. Билль о правах в значительной степени решили проблему эмансипации общества от государства, поэтому английские просветители, дав теоретическое обоснование произошедшим изменениям, в дальнейшем не уделяли большого внимания политике, а сосредоточились на проблемах веротерпимости и светской этики. Нацеленность английского Просвещения на практические дела отразила его этика, стремившаяся согласовать христианские установки с индивидуализмом. Провозглашая высшей целью счастье человека и выступая в защиту индивидуальных прав, свобод и частного интереса, английские просветители нередко приходили к моральному оправданию эгоизма. Такую этику разумного эгоизма представляли Б. Мандевиль и И. Бентам. В условиях быстрого технического прогресса и возраставшего экономического могущества Англии Просвещению в начале 18 в. был свойствен социальный оптимизм. Большой популярностью пользовалось учение о всеобщей гармонии (Э. Э.-К. Шефтсбери и др.). Просветители прославляли экономическое процветание, пафос покорения природы, предприимчивого человека, не теряющего присутствия духа в самых тяжёлых обстоятельствах. Д. Дефо первым представил современного ему буржуа как «естественного человека». Однако подобный оптимизм разделяли не все просветители. Согласно Дж. Свифту («Путешествие Гулливера»), в реальном обществе не существует ни гармонии, ни добродетели. Борьба двух противоположных тенденций пронизывает романы Г. Филдинга: идеализированный «естественный человек» с его добродетелями одерживает верх над силами эгоизма и своекорыстия. В романах Т. Смоллетта не доброта, а эгоизм, беспринципность, жадность выступают как главные свойства человеческой природы. Вместе с тем просветители пытались выработать способы социализации эгоизма. Их усилиями была создана работающая модель рационального типа жизненно-практических отношений между людьми, согласно которой одним из важнейших этических качеств человека считалась его способность к общению, взаимодействию с другими людьми (членство в клубах, масонских ложах, политических собраниях и т. д.).

Шотландские просветители, сознавая невозможность добиться возвращения независимости после заключения унии с Англией в 1707 г., призывали сосредоточиться на развитии экономики и культуры своей страны. Э. Флетчер, Д. Юм, А. Смит и другие мыслители более широко толковали условия реализации нравственной свободы и гражданской доблести, доказывая, что этого можно достигнуть участием в хозяйственной и общественной деятельности, интеллектуальных занятиях ради будущего процветания родины.

Просвещение во Франции

Просвещение во Франции испытало сильное влияние картезианства, английский философии 17 в. и творчества французских моралистов 17 в. (Ж. де Лабрюйер, Ф. де Ларошфуко и др.). В то же время возникновение новых идей было вызвано запросами аристократического общества, ощутившего большую свободу после смерти Людовика XIV. Просветители заимствовали у него салонную форму общения. Некоторые из них сами устраивали салоны (К. А. Гельвеций, П. А. Гольбах), других – незнатного происхождения (Вольтер, Д. Дидро, Ж.-Ж. Руссо) – радушно принимали в домах аристократов. Французские просветители, в отличие от английских, были склонны к отвлечённому теоретизированию. Их в большей степени привлекали теоретическая смелость, оригинальная форма выражения идеи, нежели возможность воплощения этой идеи на практике. Стремление к более неформальному общению с единомышленниками породило новый вид объединения – кружки по интересам (философские, научные, литературные; например, кружок энциклопедистов, в который входили Дидро, Гольбах, Гельвеций, М. Ж. Кондорсе и др., участвовавшие в создании «Энциклопедии»). Находясь в оппозиции, большая часть французских просветителей была лишена возможности испытать себя практическими делами. Их отличала склонность к идеализации минувших эпох, особенно республиканского строя античности (Руссо). Единственной группой просветителей, которые смогли применить на практике свои идеи, стали физиократы (Ф. Кенэ, А. Р. Ж. Тюрго). К этой группе экономистов прислушивались правительственные круги, в 1774 г. Тюрго был назначен генеральным контролёром финансов.

Значительное влияние на французское Просвещение оказал его конфликт с галликанской Церковью, не допускавшей компромисса в отношении церковных догм и осуществлявшей жёсткую цензуру. Осуждая суеверия и критикуя Церковь, многие просветители (Ш. Л. Монтескьё, Вольтер) не ставили под сомнение христианскую религию в целом, видя в ней «узду, необходимую для народа». Руссо призывал очистить христианство от суеверий и обрядовой стороны. В то же время существовало течение, которое отвергало религию, проповедовало материализм (Гельвеций, Гольбах, Дидро) и отрицало существование Бога.

Во 2-й половине 18 в. во французском Просвещении произошла дифференциация. Несмотря на неизменность основных ценностей, часть просветителей, разочаровавшись в спекулятивной философии, обратилась к актуальным проблемам социального и экономического развития (Тюрго, Ж. Неккер, А. Лавуазье). Другие (в частности, Руссо), отойдя от рационалистического метода познания и провозглашая целью очищение нравов, обратились к сенсуализму и созданию проектов идеального общественного строя. Согласно Руссо, последствия прогресса противоречивы – по мере развития цивилизации усугубляется неравенство. Руссо принадлежит разработка теории о народном суверенитете, согласно которой народ обладает высшей властью и имеет право смещать любых должностных лиц. Социальный и политический идеал Руссо имел ярко выраженные черты утопии, свойственной философии французского Просвещения. Отход от христианской традиции и утверждение культа человеческого разума способствовали возникновению различных проектов идеального общественного строя (Г. Б. де Мабли, Ж. Мелье и др.).

Представители т. н. высокого Просвещения (Вольтер, Дидро и др.), интегрированные в общество «старого порядка», не призывали к ниспровержению существующего строя. Однако к концу 18 в. появилось новое поколение – представители т. н. низкого Просвещения (Ж. П. Бриссо, Ж. П. Марат и др.), желавшие также подняться по социальной лестнице благодаря литературному таланту, но не сумевшие этого сделать по ряду причин (неразвитость книжного рынка, отсутствие покровителей и т. д.). В этой среде идеи «высокого Просвещения» принимали упрощённый вид, доступный для массового восприятия. В преддверии революции во французском Просвещении распространилась идея нравственного возрождения общества политическими методами – народным восстанием, огосударствлением широких сфер общественной жизни и т. д., что вместе с идеей Руссо о народе-суверене было впоследствии использовано для обоснования якобинского террора.

Просвещение в Италии

Особенностью Просвещения в Италии стал отказ от теоретизирования и нацеленность на решение конкретных задач, главным образом в сфере экономики и юриспруденции. Особый интерес итальянских просветителей вызывали вопросы экономики, рационального ведения хозяйства, финансовой политики государства. В Неаполе была учреждена первая в мире кафедра политической экономии – её возглавил А. Дженовези. Большое влияние на просветительскую мысль Европы и Северной Америки оказала книга Ч. Беккариа «О преступлениях и наказаниях», отрицавшая смертную казнь и требовавшая пропорциональности наказания преступлению.

Просвещение в Германии

Специфику Просвещения в Германии определили политическая раздробленность, княжеский абсолютизм, принявший характер тирании, а также слабое экономическое развитие германских земель. Одной из особенностей германского Просвещения стало то, что часто инициатива обсуждения новых идей исходила от правителя (например, в Пруссии во время правления Фридриха II Великого, в Австрии во времена Марии Терезии и Иосифа II). В связи с этим его отличало особое внимание к проблемам культуры, науки, философии, а не к практическим вопросам политики и экономики. Немецкие просветители не отрицали социальную роль Церкви и охотно сотрудничали со светскими властями в проведении политики реформ. Это объяснялось во многом социальным статусом носителей новых идей, каковыми были в основном дворяне, чиновничество и другие социальные группы, тесно связанные с государством и зависимые от него. Государственная служба для них являлась основным каналом повышения социального статуса, источником дохода, для её получения было необходимо соответствующее образование и воспитание. Кроме личных мотивов, просветителей связывали с государством религиозная и философская традиции. Идеи естественного права и общественного договора уживались в политических теориях немецких просветителей с апологией абсолютизма (С. фон Пуфендорф, К. Томазий, Х. фон Вольф). В их концепциях монарх выступал единственным толкователем и проводником естественного права, защитником блага подданных, гарантом мира и справедливости в государстве. Вместе с тем с конца 1750-х гг. усилилась критика политического строя (например, Г. Э. Лессинг с его обличением феодальной тирании и религиозной нетерпимости). Одной из главных фигур немецкого Просвещения стал И. Г. Гердер, утверждавший единство исторического процесса и отстаивавший принцип естественной эволюции.

С ростом во Франции с 1780-х гг. антиклерикального и политического радикализма в Германии стала усиливаться критика просветительского рационализма и универсализма, что свидетельствовало о кризисе немецкого Просвещения. В этих условиях сформировались революционно-демократическая идеология (немецкие «якобинцы» – Г. Форстер, В. Л. Векрлин, А. Ребман) и т. н. веймарский классицизм Гёте и Ф. Шиллера (веймарского периода их жизни), устремивших свои поиски в сторону гуманистической морали, эстетического воспитания как средства разрешения противоречий культуры и истории. В немецкой просветительской мысли впервые был поставлен вопрос о самой сути Просвещения. С выступления М. Мендельсона «Что такое Просвещение» в 1784 г. началась дискуссия, в которой приняли участие Гердер, И. Кант и др. Согласно Канту, Просвещение заключалось в раскрепощении людей путём получения знания, способности мыслить, не подчиняясь авторитету духовных или светских властей.

Просвещение в других государствах Европы

В Испании Просвещение носило по преимуществу умеренный характер (П. Р. де Кампоманес, Г. М. де Ховельянос), что в большей степени способствовало формированию испанского варианта просвещённого абсолютизма.

У народов Центральной, Юго-Восточной и Восточной Европы на идеологию Просвещения большое влияние оказывала борьба за национальное освобождение. Для неё был характерен синтез национально-патриотических традиций с идеями, заимствованными у западноевропейских просветителей. Наиболее яркое проявление Просвещения в этом регионе находило в филологии (защита национального языка) и в исторической науке (разработка национальной истории, идея исторической общности славян – у славянских народов). В Польше Просвещение во 2-й половине 18 – начале 19 вв. было тесно связано с национально-освободительным движением. Во главе польского Просвещения стояли находившиеся под влиянием французских просветителей Г. Коллонтай, С. Сташиц – антиклерикалы, материалисты, противники сословного строя и крепостного права, проповедовавшие идеи т. н. польского якобинства, отстаивавшие принципы равноправия наций, неприкосновенности национального суверенитета, естественного права и общественного договора. Главной фигурой южнославянского Просвещения являлся сербский философ-рационалист Д. Обрадович, испытавший влияние идей английского Просвещения. Большое значение имело творчество и деятельность словенского поэта-просветителя В. Водника, создателя первой словенской газеты, хорватского писателя-просветителя М. А. Рельковича и др. В Венгрии развитие просветительских идей связано с именами философа-материалиста, писателя, родоначальника венгерского Просвещения Д. Бешшеньси, поэта В. Чоконаи-Витеза. Крупными представителями чешского Просвещения являлись Г. Добнер, историк Ф. М. Пельцль, а также другие представители «Будителей». В Болгарии Просвещение, развивавшееся в 19 в., связано с деятельностью И. Селиминского, находившегося под влиянием французских и немецких просветителей.

Просвещение в Северной и Южной Америке

С середины 18 в. новые идеи стали распространяться в Северной Америке (североамериканских колониях Великобритании). Американских просветителей (Б. Франклин, Т. Джефферсон, Т. Пейн) интересовали в первую очередь проблемы политики, что было обусловлено борьбой за независимость и нашло отражение в обосновании права народа на расторжение общественного договора с правителем-тираном.

В конце 18 – начале 19 вв. идеи Просвещения широко распространились в Латинской Америке. Х. Б. Диас де Гамарра (Новая Испания) отстаивал притязания разума на объяснение явлений мира. С. Родригес (Венесуэла) горячо пропагандировал концепции Ж.-Ж. Руссо. Школу энциклопедистов прошёл А. Бельо. Воспитанные на идеях Просвещения С. Боливар, А. Нариньо и др. возглавили Войну за независимость в Латинской Америке.

Просвещение в Российской империи

В России, как и в Западной Европе, Просвещение представляло собой процесс духовной и интеллектуальной трансформации. Наличие родственных черт в российском и западноевропейском Просвещении обусловило совпадение основных идей Просвещения в России и на Западе, сходство его проявлений в философии, искусстве, литературе и других формах духовной жизни.

Расцвет раннего русского Просвещения относится к 1760–1780-м гг., когда появились произведения М. М. Щербатова, И. Н. Болтина, Н. И. Новикова, Д. И. Фонвизина, А. Я. Поленова, философа и переводчика Я. П. Козельского («Философические предложения», 1768; современное издание – 2009), С. Е. Десницкого, переводы сочинений Вольтера, публиковавшиеся И. Г. Рахманиновым (1780-е гг.), и др. Первые русские просветители возлагали надежды на «просвещённого монарха», справедливые законы, основанные на естественном праве, смягчение нравов в результате распространения образования и правильного воспитания; выступали за пробуждение национального самосознания и достоинства личности, за патриотизм, равно чуждый и национальной спеси, и «чужебесию». Осуждались помещичье «жестокосердие», невежество, грубость нравов как результат растлевающего влияния крепостнических отношений. Идеал русского просветителя – гуманный, образованный, внимательный к своим крестьянам дворянин, такой как персонажи комедии Д. И. Фонвизина «Недоросль» Стародум и Правдин. Просветители уделяли особое внимание организации воспитания юношества и сбору для этого материальных пожертвований, основали Учительскую (Педагогическую) (1779–1786) и Переводческую (Филологическую) (1782–1786) семинарии, Собрание университетских питомцев (1781–1789) и «Дружеское учёное общество» (1782–1786) при Московском университете; на ниве просвещения особенно выделялся И. Г. Шварц.

Большинство русских просветителей входили в тайные масонские ложи, часть из них проявляла политическую активность. Это насторожило императрицу Екатерину II, состоявшую в переписке со многими европейскими просветителями и прослывшую среди них «мудрецом на троне». В конце 1770-х гг. она удалила ряд видных масонов-просветителей из столицы в Москву, а в 1782 г. утвердила Устав благочиния, запрещавший деятельность в России любых тайных обществ. Цензурным запретам и искажениям подверглась диссертация Д. С. Аничкова о происхождении религии [«Разсуждение из натуральной богословии о начале и произшествии натуральнаго богопочитания» (1769)], Н. И. Новиков был заключён в Шлиссельбургскую крепость. А. Н. Радищев, автор книги «Путешествие из Петербурга в Москву» (1790), фактически явившийся родоначальником революционного направления в русском Просвещении, выслан в Сибирь. Наследие европейских и русских просветителей оказало огромное влияние на формирование мировоззрения декабристов.

Завершение эпохи Просвещения часто связывается с Французской революцией 18 в., поскольку идеи просветителей, способствовавшие оправданию якобинского террора, стали восприниматься с настороженностью. Однако предпринимавшиеся после разгрома наполеоновской Франции попытки реставрации старых порядков не смогли перечеркнуть важнейшие завоевания Просвещения, связанные с рационализацией и секуляризацией мысли, бурным развитием естественных и общественных наук, изменениями в духовной культуре и повседневной жизни. Взгляды просветителей легли в основу идеологии либерализма, использовались для обоснования Июльской революции 1830 г. и Бельгийской революции 1830 г., оказали влияние на политику многих европейских государей в 1-й половине 19 в.

Дата публикации:  27 сентября 2022 г. в 13:22 (GMT+3)

Понравилась статья? Поделить с друзьями:
  • Эпоха застоя как пишется
  • Эпоха великих географических открытий как пишется
  • Эпоха барокко как пишется
  • Эпольман круазе как пишется
  • Эпл как пишется на английском языке